| ||
The Editorial Problem of Final Authorial Intention
by
G. Thomas
Tanselle
[*]
Scholarly editors may disagree about many things, but they are in general agreement that their goal is to discover exactly what an author wrote and to determine what form of his work he wished the public to have. There may be some difference of opinion about the best way of achieving that goal; but if the edition is to be a work of scholarship—a historical reconstruction—the goal itself must involve the author's "intention." The centrality of that concept to scholarly editing can be illustrated by W. W. Greg's "The Rationale of Copy-Text,"[1] which, in the quarter century since it first appeared, has established itself as the most influential document in modern editorial theory. What Greg succeeded in accomplishing was to provide a rationale for selecting, and then emending, a basic text in those cases in which the choice was not made obvious by the historical,
Although Greg did not address himself to the question of a precise definition of "author's intention," it is clear from such a summary that he considered the goal of an edition—and he was speaking of an "old-spelling critical edition"—to be the reconstruction of a text representing the author's final wishes about the version of his work to be presented to the public. In Fredson Bowers's words, the task is "to approximate as nearly as possible an inferential authorial fair copy, or other ultimately authoritative document";[2] or, as he put it another time, following Greg's theory will produce "the nearest approximation in every respect of the author's final intentions."[3] If an author can be shown to have gone over his work with scrupulous care for a revised edition, examining accidentals as well as substantives, the revised edition (as the closest edition to an "ultimately authoritative document") would become the copy-text. Such a situation does not arise in most
Just what is meant by "author's final intention," however, has not been made entirely clear, although at first glance the concept may seem so self-evident as not to require formal definition. Its use in connection with editing suggests that an editor's task is not to "improve" upon an author's decisions, even when he believes that the author made an unwise revision, and that an editor's judgment is directed toward the recovery of what the author wrote, not toward an evaluation of the effectiveness of the author's revisions.[6] Furthermore, the concept, as a goal of editing, would seem clearly to imply that, when an editor has strong reason to attribute a revision to the author, he will accept that revision as "final" on the grounds that, coming second, it represents the author's considered and more mature judgment. Greg suggests that this procedure is equally valid for dealing with wholesale revision when he writes, "If a work has been entirely rewritten, and is printed from a new manuscript, . . . the revised edition will be a substantive one, and as such will presumably be chosen by the editor as his copy-text" (p. 389).
It is true that, in many instances, the simple interpretation of
I
The question of the meaning of "intention," both in general terms and in relation to works of art, involves many complex philosophical issues and has been widely debated.[7] Probably the best-known and most influential discussion of this subject in relation to literary works is W. K. Wimsatt and Monroe C. Beardsley's 1946 essay, "The Intentional Fallacy," which takes the point of view that the author's intention is irrelevant to the process of literary interpretation and evaluation.[8] Although the essay is not as clear as it might be in distinguishing
One might at first conclude, therefore, that such discussions of intention are irrelevant to editorial work, conceived of as operating at an anterior stage and providing the material for the critic to analyze. If, in other words, one could assert that the editor's task does not involve critical decisions but only the recovery of factual information about what word or mark of punctuation the author wanted to have at each point in his text, one could then say that any effort to understand or assess the "meaning" of the text is an entirely separate matter and that the possibility of an "intentional fallacy" applies only to this interpretive and evaluative activity.[12] It is immediately apparent, however, that the job of the editor cannot be so regarded. If the aim of the editor is to establish the text as the author wished to have it presented to the public (and we shall postpone any consideration of other possible editorial aims), he cannot divorce himself from the "meaning" of the text, for, however much documentary evidence he may have, he can never have enough to relieve himself of the necessity
It is clear, then, as soon as one starts to talk about "intention," that
various kinds of intention need to be distinguished, and many of the recent
discussions of intention in literature do attempt to subdivide the concept.
Thus T. M. Gang differentiates between "practical intention" (intention "to
achieve a certain result") and "literary intention" (intention to convey "a
certain significance"); John Kemp distinguishes between "immediate
intention" (that which a man "intends, or sets himself, to do") and "ulterior
intention" ("that which he intends or hopes to achieve as a result of doing
what he does"); Morse Peckham discriminates between "mediated intention"
("a statement or other sign") and "immediate intention" ("metaphorical
extension of mediated intention into the area of 'mind'"); and Quentin
Skinner, borrowing terms from J. L. Austin's How to Do
Of such classifications of intention, one of the clearest and most useful has been set forth by Michael Hancher.[15] In his view, "author's intentions" can be divided into three types: (1) "programmatic intention"—"the author's intention to make something or other"; (2) "active intention"—"the author's intention to be (understood as) acting in some way or other"; and (3) "final intention"—"the author's intention to cause something or other to happen." The first refers to the author's general plan to write a sonnet, say, or a realistic novel;
Before pursuing the implications of that argument, we should pause long enough to note that what editors in the tradition of Greg are likely to call "final intention" does not correspond to what Hancher here calls "final intention." Rather, the intention with which editors are concerned is Hancher's "active intention," the intention that the work "mean (and be taken to mean) something or other" (p. 831). The fact that an editor, as briefly suggested above, must examine both the author's intention to use a particular word and the author's intention to mean a particular thing in the work as a whole—indeed, must make decisions about the first in the light of the second—is adequately accommodated in Hancher's concept of "active intention." Hancher's initial illustration of the concept includes comment on Hopkins's intention in using "buckle" in "The Windhover" as well as on his intention for the meaning of "the whole action of that poem." Because an intention regarding the meaning of a work as a whole may not always seem distinct from a programmatic intention, Hancher later recognizes that a programmatic intention may "involve a kind of active intention" (p. 836) but distinguishes between such "projected active intention" and the "active intention that ultimately defines the meaning of the completed text" (p. 837). Therefore "active intention," as he defines it, does cover the authorial intentions with which an editor has to deal. Accordingly, whenever I speak of "intention," unless otherwise specified, I am referring to the kind of intention included in Hancher's concept of "active intention"; even when I use the term "final intention," in conformity with the common practice of editors, the word "intention" still refers to the same concept (and not to what Hancher calls "final intention")—though just what "final" may mean in the phrase remains to be examined later.
It can readily be inferred from what I have already said about Hancher's conclusion that he does not belong to that group of critics
How, then, is the author's intended meaning to be discovered? In answering that question, one is inevitably drawn back to the work itself as the most reliable documentary evidence as to what the author intended. If he made no statement setting forth his intention, one has
The bearing of these ideas on the task of the editor is worth making explicit. At the start, the editor has settled one important question through his definition of his goal: he is concerned with establishing the text as intended by the author, and thus he has no doubts about the relevance of the author's intention to his undertaking. But then he recognizes that the most reliable source of information about the author's intention in a given work is that work itself. He will take other information into account, but he must always measure it finally against the very text which is the subject of his inquiry. The editor may at first feel that his job is different from the critic's in that he is concerned with establishing intended wording, not with explicating intended meaning. That is, he may think (in Austin's terms) that he is dealing only with the author's locutionary act, not his illocutionary act. But he soon realizes that his discovery of textual errors or his choice among textual variants involves his understanding of the intended meaning of the text. For if either of two alternative words makes sense at a given point, the determination of which the author intended clearly involves more than his locutionary act.[26] Greg's
The key to the use of the work as evidence of its author's intended meaning must lie in the approach which the critic (editor) takes.[27] One critic may believe that he has found through internal evidence the most satisfactory explication of a work and may not be interested in whether or not this meaning was intended by the author.[28] Another critic, who wishes to find the author's intended meaning, will read the work in the light of all the historical and biographical evidence he can locate and may thereby eliminate certain meanings as ones which the author could not have intended;[29] his interpretation of the text is thus limited by certain external information, but his positive evidence still comes from the text itself. If I hastily dash off a message for someone and the recipient finds it ambiguous, he will attempt to rule out certain meanings on the basis of what he knows of me and of the circumstances which occasioned the message; what he finally concludes to be my intended meaning, however, cannot be based merely on what the external evidence suggests I would be likely to say in that situation but must rest on the words I actually did use. Furthermore,
The scholarly editor is in the same position as the critic who is concerned with the author's intended meaning. Regardless of how many meanings he finds in the text, the scholarly editor makes corrections or emendations on the basis of the one he judges most likely to have been the author's intended meaning. Hancher speaks of a science of interpretation, in which the critic's aim is to determine the "authorized" or intended meaning, and an art of interpretation, in which the critic's aim is to find the most satisfying meaning according to his own "norms of value."[30] Some critics would protest that all meanings are part of an intended complex combination of meanings, intended in the sense that the author, whether consciously or unconsciously, created a structure in which they could be discovered. But this appeal to "subconscious intention," as T. M. Gang has indicated,[31] implies a universal set of relationships between consciously produced patterns and their subconscious origins—relationships which, if they are always in operation, cannot be specifically intended and are always available for anyone to discern. One need not deny that such meanings can be found in the work and that they may be valuable (and offer revealing insights into the author's personality and motivation) in order to believe that "intention" cannot be a useful concept if it is made so broad as to cover all potentially discoverable meanings. It is certainly true that neither the author nor anyone else can construct an explanatory paraphrase which is the exact equivalent of the work itself; but
An editor could, of course, emend a text so that it would, in his view, be a more successful expression of that meaning which he finds most valuable in it; but his activity would have nothing to do with the author. In Hancher's terms, he would be engaging in the "art" of interpretation—or, rather, editing on the basis of that kind of interpretation. A scholarly editor sets as his goal the reconstruction of the text intended by the author. In Hancher's terms, he is engaging in the "science," not the art, of interpretation—but it is still interpretation and entails critical thinking. His defined approach is what controls the use he makes of what he finds in the work. He will probably find more than one meaning there, but his specialized knowledge places him in a privileged position for assessing which of them can most reasonably be regarded as the author's.[32] The text he produces can, like any other text, be the subject of critical speculation by those who have no interest in the author's intention; but it can also serve the needs of those critics who are concerned with the work as the product of a particular mind. That an interpretation by one of the former turns out to seem more satisfying to many readers than an interpretation by one of the latter has no bearing on the importance or desirability of the task which the scholarly editor has set himself.
These considerations suggest, first of all, that editing is a critical activity and that the scholarly editor cannot avoid coming to terms with the critical problem of authorial intention. Second, there is a specific and clearly defined aspect of the broad concept of "intention" which is the appropriate concern of the scholarly editor—the intention of the author to have particular words and marks of punctuation constitute his text and the intention that such a text carry a particular
II
An editor who has given some attention to such preliminary questions has at least begun to reach an understanding of "authorial intention." But there are a number of further questions which arise as he attempts to make judgments in the light of this conception of intention. Perhaps the most common editorial situation is that in which the editor must decide whether a given variant reading is a revision by the author or an alteration (conscious or inadvertent) by someone else. In these cases, at least one intermediate stage of documentary evidence is lacking, and the editor is trying to determine from the surviving material those changes which the author made in that now missing document. He must also face the question whether it is ever possible to think of changes not made by the author as nevertheless fulfilling, or contributing to, the author's intention.
The basic situation can be illustrated by Sherwood Anderson's A Story Teller's Story (1924). The only surviving prepublication text of this work is the typescript printer's copy, which bears revisions by three people: Anderson himself, Paul Rosenfeld, and E. T. Booth, the publisher's editor. One has direct evidence, therefore, for assigning the responsibility for each of these alterations; but the first printing of the book (Huebsch, 1924) contains additional changes, not marked on the surviving typescript and presumably entered on the now lost proofs. Deciding which of these changes were made by Anderson is the central task in editing this book.[33] What the editor has to do is to familiarize himself with all the available relevant evidence—bibliographical, historical, biographical. He may then find that some of it is
The same observations can be made about situations involving variants between printed editions. In these cases the missing documents are the author's marked copy of the earlier edition (or its proofs, or whatever served as printer's copy for the edition set later) and the marked proofs of the later edition. If no document survives which antedates the proofs of the earliest setting of the text, then of course one is dealing with texts which have already been subjected to the routine of the printing- or publishing-house. Thus the essential difference between this situation and the one described above is that here the editor is working at a greater remove from the author's fair-copy manuscript or typescript; but his approach to the problem remains the same. For instance, neither the manuscript of The Rise of Silas Lapham nor the proofs set from it survive; and the history of the early printed texts, which vary from one another substantively at a number of points, is such that one text might contain the later readings in one part of the book and another the later readings in a different part. So for any given variant, the editor must first try to determine the order of the readings and then decide whether the later one could be an authorial revision or correction. At one point in Chapter 19 Irene's complexion is described as "snow-white" in the serialized magazine text and as "colourless" in the first book edition
Once the editor has made his judgments as to which variants are attributable to the author and which to someone else, he must consider the exact status of the latter group. Are all variants for which someone other than the author is responsible to be rejected outright, or is it conceivable that the author's intention may sometimes be fulfilled by other persons? It is not only conceivable but unquestionably true that others can and do sometimes correct an author's writing and in the process fulfill his intention. An author may write down one word but be thinking of a different one, or in reading proofs he may fail to notice a printer's error which creates a new word. When these erroneous words are plausible in their contexts, they may never be recognized by anyone as erroneous; but when one of them does not make sense, and when the correct word is obvious, anyone who makes the correction is carrying out the author's intention. Frequently an editor may believe that a particular word cannot have been intended but is not certain just what the intended word should be; only his critical assessment of the whole matter can determine whether it is preferable in that case to let the questionable word stand and call attention to the problem in a note or to substitute a word which catches the apparent intended sense (again, of course, with an explanation), even though that word may not be the exact one which the author had in mind. In the typescript of A Story Teller's Story, then, alterations in the hand of E. T. Booth cannot simply be dismissed; they must be inspected carefully, because Booth may have noticed places where the typescript reading certainly (or almost certainly) cannot have been Anderson's intended reading, and there is always the chance that an editor might otherwise fail to detect some of them.
An examination of Booth's revisions, however, leads to a more difficult question. Since Booth was the editor for the publisher, can one
The importance, for editorial practice, of settling this question in general terms is evident. When an editor faces a choice for copy-text between a fair-copy manuscript (or printer's copy) and a first impression, he needs to have—in the absence of convincing evidence—a general policy to fall back on, a policy based on the inherent probabilities in such situations. Of course, if the editor has convincing evidence— not merely the author's statements but detailed information about the author's methods of going over proofs—he can make his decision on that basis. But, as is more likely to be the case, if the evidence is not sufficient for making a competent decision, the editor must have further guidance. Greg's rationale, pointing out the usual deterioration of a text (particularly its accidentals) from one manuscript or edition to another, leads the editor back to the fair-copy manuscript or the earliest extant text which follows it. There has been some disagreement with this position, however, based on the view that the author's intention encompasses the activities which take place in the step from manuscript (or typescript) to print and that the intention is not "final" until the text conforms to the standards which will make it publishable. Philip Gaskell concludes that "in most cases the editor will choose as copy-text an early printed edition, not the manuscript"; the accidentals of the manuscript, he says, "the author would himself have been prepared—or might have preferred—to discard."[41] James Thorpe agrees:
Such arguments for preferring the first edition to the manuscript seem to me misguided. While it is true that most authors have the intention of getting published, such an intention is of a different order from their intention to have certain words and punctuation, resulting in a certain meaning, in their text. The intention of writing something publishable is what Hancher would call a "programmatic intention"; what the editor is properly concerned with, as we have seen, is the author's "active intention" manifested in the work. There is no reason why in some instances an author's active intention might not conflict with his programmatic intention. That an author may submit to various publishing-house alterations as a routine procedure in the process of publication does not amount to his changing his active intention about what his writing is to consist of. To say that he "expects" or is prepared to have certain changes made by the printer or publisher is not the same as to say that he prefers or wishes to have them made; to take his implicit approval of these changes on the proofs (or the printer's copy) as a sign that he is now more satisfied with his text is to ignore the many external factors (Melville's "Time, Strength, Cash, and Patience") which at this stage might prevent him from restoring readings that he actively desired. It is of little help to survey what writers in the past have said on the subject of publishers' alterations of their spelling and punctuation, even if there were a valid statistical basis for concluding, as Thorpe does, that most are "of the indifferent persuasion" (p. 151). Indifference is far from suggesting intention; and the motivation for the indifference would in each case have to be examined in order to know how to interpret the statements. But if the attitudes of writers toward this question cannot be fairly generalized about, the views and practices of printers and publishers can. Printers' manuals, after all, are normative and instructional statements, offering a far more trustworthy basis for generalization than individual authors' expressions of their own attitudes. Thorpe himself, after quoting from various manuals, recognizes that, for most of the period with which he is concerned, "it has been the printers (particularly the compositors and proofreaders) who have
Whether there is sufficient evidence in a given case to justify taking the first edition rather than the manuscript as copy-text is a matter of judgment. What the editor must attempt to assess is whether the author genuinely preferred the changes made by the publisher's reader or whether he merely acquiesced in them. The idea that an author can actively intend in his work a revision made by someone else depends in effect on the extent to which the two can be regarded as voluntary collaborators. Since collaboration implies shared responsibility, the "author's intention" in a collaborative effort results from a merging of the separate intentions of the individual authors; the final result is thus intended by each of the authors. A work need not be signed with more than one name, of course, for it to be a collaboration. Nor is it necessary for the authors involved to perform equal shares of the work; indeed, two people may collaborate only on certain aspects of a work, and their joint intention would apply only to the words or elements involved. The facsimile edition of the revised manuscript-typescript of The Waste Land offers a rare opportunity to observe some of the collaboration which can underlie a great work. In certain passages Pound's revisions (such as "demobbed" in line 139) or deletions (as in "Death by Water") actually constitute collaboration, though there are other places where Eliot rejects Pound's suggestions (as in the lines on Saint Mary Woolnoth, lines 67-68). That the work is to some extent collaborative is implied by Valerie Eliot's comment, in her description of "Editorial Policy," that "It has been difficult to decide who cancelled certain lines, especially when both Eliot and Pound have worked on them together."[44] A study of this facsimile does not suggest that an editor should incorporate into the text of the poem the lines which Pound rejected and Eliot did not restore; one can argue that at those points Eliot's intention merged
The question, posed earlier, of whether it makes sense to believe that an author can ask someone else to carry out his intention in some respect may now be answered in the negative. By definition, an author's active intention cannot include projected activity and cannot include activity of which he is not in control. The ultimate example of delegated intention in writing would be for a person to ask someone else to write an entire work for him; if he then announced that it represented his "intention," he could only mean his intention to write a certain kind of work (his programmatic intention), for his active intention would not be involved. The same is true regardless of what portion or aspect of a work is at issue, as long as the element contributed by someone other than the author must be described with such expressions as "It is what the author expected to have done" or "It is what the author would have done if he had found time." However, if an author accepts what someone else has done not in a spirit of acquiescence but of active collaboration, the result does represent his active intention. Since the scholarly editor, in establishing a text, is concerned with an author's active intention in that text, he can accept into the text what he knows (or strongly believes) to be initially the work of someone else only when it can be regarded as having been accepted by the primary author as a true collaboration. This approach does not alter the crucial role which the editor's judgment plays in evaluating evidence, but it may provide a useful framework into which that evidence can be placed. It also suggests the relative infrequency with which publishers' alterations can be taken to supersede an author's known practice in a prepublication stage of his work.
III
After the editor has separated authorial from nonauthorial alterations and has decided how to treat the nonauthorial ones, he still faces the question of how to define "final" with respect to the authorial variants. Normally, of course, when there are two authorial readings at a given point and their sequence can be determined, the later one is taken to represent the author's "final intention." However, there are in general two kinds of situations in which this view of "final
The editorial problem in both cases usually reduces itself to quantitative terms: when the authorial variants are few in number, it makes little practical difference if an editor selects one group of readings as "final" and incorporates them into his text, since the reader will be able without much difficulty to analyze the variants for himself and come to his own conclusions about the way in which these variants alter the total effect of the work; but when the number of variants is great, the system of presenting one final text with variant readings in notes is less satisfactory, and the only practical solution is to produce more than one text (perhaps arranged in parallel columns), each representing a different "intention."[46] That the recognition of more than one valid text of a given work is often forced on an editor by the practical exigencies of recording variant readings should not obscure the fact that the theoretical problem of determining "final" authorial intention has no necessary connection with the quantity of variants.
Turning to the first of the two categories—in which an author's revisions produce, in a manner of speaking, a new work—one can identify several patterns. The most clear-cut involves those situations in which the author's revisions reflect motives which make it impossible for an editor to accept the later version of a work as truly representing the author's intention, even though, in temporal terms, this version is "final." If, for instance, an author deletes passages for the purpose of producing a condensation or simplifies the language to make the work appropriate for younger readers, the special motives in each case prevent the resulting revisions from being definitive. The revised version, in such cases, does not represent a refinement of the work as previously "completed" but a new work conceived for different purposes;
A similar situation occurs when an author makes revisions, not because he wishes to, but because he is asked or compelled to. Herman Melville, after the publication of Typee (1846), was asked by his American publisher, Wiley & Putnam, to soften his criticism of the missionaries in the South Seas for a revised edition, and in July 1846 he complied by deleting about thirty-six pages of material and revising other passages. These changes alter the tone of the book and are not in keeping with the spirit of the original version. There is no question that Melville is responsible for the changes, and in this sense they are "final"; but they represent not so much his intention as his acquiescence. Under these circumstances, an editor is justified in rejecting the revisions and adopting the original readings as best reflecting the author's "final intention"; in fact, to accept the readings which are final in chronological terms would distort that intention. But again the two types of revision must be separated, for Melville made some revisions in July 1846 which had no connection with the expurgation of political, religious, and sexual references—and these an editor would
A further related problem—the weight to be attached to an author's statement about his revisions—can also be illustrated by the Typee case. After removing the passages on the missionaries from the American edition, Melville wrote to John Murray, his English publisher, "Such passages are altogether foreign to the adventure, & altho' they may possess a temporary interest now, to some, yet so far as the wide & permanent popularity of the work is conserned [sic], their exclusion will certainly be beneficial." One could argue that Melville is simply making the best of the situation, that he is rationalizing the changes and trying to convince himself that they are for the better; on the other side, one could say that here is a strong statement from the author about his "intention" and that the author's wishes, so stated, must be respected. However, in the same way that an author may make revisions which do not reflect his ultimate wishes about his work, he may also make statements which, for various reasons, are less than completely candid. In the end, one cannot automatically accept such statements at face value; as in any historical research, statements can only be interpreted by placing them in their context, by reconstructing as fully as possible the course of events which led up to them. The publisher, in the case of Typee, and not the author, initiated the revisions, and there is no evidence, internal or external, to suggest that they are the kinds of changes Melville would have made without pressure from someone else; even his statement implies that the revised work is in a sense a different work, stemming from a different set of programmatic intentions—aimed at producing a permanently popular work, not dated by discussions of current issues. After these considerations, an editor need not feel that Melville's statement makes the case for rejecting the expurgations any less strong.[50] Such statements
This treatment of author's statements has certain further implications. The essential issue, stated baldly, is whether an editor can presume to reverse an author's decision. Even if Melville did not want to revise Typee, the fact remains that he did so and even asserted decisively that the result was an improvement. Is it not the author's prerogative to determine the ultimate form of his work? Suppose that Melville meant what he said and that, even though he would not have made the revisions without external influence, he was sincerely convinced that he had done the right thing. Most editors would disagree with him, but they would also say that it is not an editor's place to determine what the author should have done. If the author has a lapse in taste, the argument goes, that lapse is a historical fact which scholarly research cannot undertake to repair. There is no answer to this argument, of course, so long as the revision was definitely an attempt to improve the work in terms of its original conception (horizontal revision). But when the revision shifts that conception and thereby produces a different work (vertical revision), the editor may only confuse matters by presenting the revised version as the basic text: if he finds the original version a more faithful representation of the author's vision, he is not abdicating his scholarly responsibility in favor of an undisciplined subjectivity if he edits that version on its own terms as a separate work (and goes on to include the variant readings of the revised edition in notes). It is one thing for an editor to impose his taste upon an author's work by choosing among variant readings solely on the basis of their appeal to him; it is quite another for him to put that taste to the service of historical understanding by allowing it to guide him in distinguishing among the levels of authorial revision and discriminating among the various artistic conceptions they represent.
The most familiar situation in which more than one "final" intention can be said to exist occurs when an author, at a later stage in his career, extensively revises a work completed years before—not because
If this point of view has been readily accepted in extreme cases of revision, it has scarcely been considered at all in instances of slight revision. But why should the quantity of alterations affect one's theoretical position? If one treats a heavily revised text as an independent work simply because the difficulties of handling the variants in any other way are overwhelming and then edits a less heavily revised work as a single text with notes because it is possible to do so, the theoretical basis of the whole operation is questionable. The idea that a revised version can be considered a separate work is sometimes said to rest on the concept of organic form—the view that form and content in a work of art are so integrated that any alteration produces a new entity. Of course, it is not necessary to adduce this concept in order to make the point: changing a word in any utterance results technically in a different utterance. Although the change of one word in a novel
If, in practice, editors are not going to regard each version as necessarily a separate work, then some rationale is required for distinguishing those instances of revision which are to be edited as separate works from those which are not. A quantitative dividing line is not logical: it would be impossible to set up a particular number of revisions, or words involved in revisions, as the test for defining a separate work in this sense.[54] What is more meaningful than the extent of the revisions is their nature. One author might make 3000 changes in his selection of adjectives and adverbs, for instance—and perhaps improve his book stylistically—without altering his original conception of the work at all; another might make only ten revisions in key passages and change the whole direction of the book. Whether or not two versions of a book are treated by an editor as independent works should depend on a qualitative, not quantitative, distinction. If revisions do not spring from the same conception of an organic whole as the original version manifested (what I have called vertical revisions), then they produce a new work, even though the actual number of new readings is small; if revisions are attempts to develop and improve the original conception (what I have called horizontal revisions), then they do not produce a separate work for practical purposes, regardless of the number of changes involved.[55] Generally, large numbers of alterations do follow from a changed conception or programmatic intention, but the point is that there is no necessary connection between the two.
In making decisions about authorial intention, an editor may be inclined to take into account a related factor, the timing of the changes. When an author, late in his life, makes revisions in an early work, one could argue that the result will almost surely constitute an effectively different work, since it is unlikely that the author will have the same conception of his work in mind as he had during the process of its original composition. James's revisions are a case in point, but the argument can be applied to other instances in which neither the extent of the changes nor the shift in intent is so pronounced. When
The role which these considerations play in editing and the critical nature of the decisions they imply are well illustrated in Bowers's edition of Stephen Crane's Maggie.[57] Crane's book was first printed privately in 1893; three years later, in order to secure publication by D. Appleton & Co., he agreed to make revisions, particularly the elimination of profanity. But, as Bowers points out, Crane's alterations were not limited to bowdlerizing: "It is clear from many examples
With some authors the possibility of multiple "final" intentions is further intensified. Instead of making one systematic revision of a work at some point later in life, they revise their work continually throughout their careers. An extreme example of this method, referred to by Bowers in the passage quoted above, is Whitman's Leaves of Grass, which was extensively revised eight times between 1855 and 1892. When an author works in this way, successive editions constitute a printed record of a developing mind. The fact that Whitman said of his final "deathbed" edition (1891-92) that any future edition should be "a copy and facsimile, indeed, of the text of these . . . pages" does not mean that critics and scholars must reject all earlier editions as works in their own right.[60] Even if Whitman came to think of the earlier editions as preliminary drafts for his final version, each of those editions was published and at the time of its publication represented a final version that he was willing to present to the public and thus his final intention as of that moment.[61] If one decides that the revisions at each stage are the kind which spring from an altered conception of the whole, one can argue that each edition of Leaves is a separate work with its own final intention. (The situation would differ from that of Henry James only in the greater number of separate works, resulting from the greater number of stages of revision.) In that case, Whitman's last text is not—as an intended work—any more "final" than his earlier texts; it merely comes later. To one taking this position, Whitman's own judgment should of course be no embarrassment; it is only a critical pronouncement about his work, not an element within the work.
These issues are raised in an acute form in connection with the poetry of W. H. Auden. Joseph Warren Beach, in The Making of the Auden Canon (1957), describes in great detail the way in which Auden continually omitted or revised passages to bring his poems into conformity with his current ideological preoccupations. In 1945, for example, he gave the poems from "In Time of War," in Beach's words, "a more distinctively religious cast than they had when first written in 1938 and published in 1939" (p. 10). Throughout his career, according to Beach, Auden displayed a faculty for "domesticating, within the frame of mind that at any moment possesses him, work conceived in some quite different frame of mind" (p. 15). In preparing a collected edition, he not only revised poems to make them "reasonably acceptable to him at a time when he was concerned that his work should be as edifying spiritually as it was imaginatively arresting" (p. 242); he also arranged the poems in alphabetical order so that their connections with previous volumes or particular stages in his career would be obscured. The situation is reminiscent of Whitman's preparation of an authorized final edition, but in Auden's case the emphasis is more clearly on ideological content than on artistic form. As with Whitman, Auden's final text can be regarded as only another text, reflecting a different conception of his work.
Beach's analysis presents, in effect, the apparatus for a critical edition in essay form—a method which, for this kind of author, is perhaps more useful than a list of variant readings, since such a list tends to suggest that the versions compared are essentially the same work. At the end of his book Beach takes up—in one of the few discussions of the subject in print—some of the editorial implications of multiple authorial intention. One can concur with his feeling of dissatisfaction about Auden's collected text and yet find a curious logic in his conclusion:
Pursuing the nature of Auden's "identity," Beach sensibly asks, "And how . . . can we question the right of an author to be his own judge as to the intent of a piece of writing, or to make it over so as to give it a new direction?" (p. 251). This, after all, is the central issue. But the answer again proves troublesome: "What I have suggested is that such a making over of a work of literary art is not to be accomplished by cutting out a few offensive passages, or by merely hanging the work in a different gallery in different company; and that it is vain to suppose that now it means something essentially different from what it did." In other words, as he goes on to say, a work of art should have "a wholeness, or integrality, that underlies all the diverse and even conflicting elements" (p. 253). It is precisely because of its "integrality," however, that any adjustments made in a work of art may turn it into a different, if no less integral, work. To say that an author's last version of a work means the same thing as his earliest is to abandon all criticism; but to find that a late version fails to supersede an early one is not to deny the author's right to do with his work as he pleases. In the end, whenever there are authorial revisions, an editor is not fulfilling his responsibility to the work of literature if he does not assess the nature of those revisions, in order to determine whether he is really dealing with only a single work.
Before glancing at the argument that this approach to editing gives the editor too much freedom to be eclectic, let us turn to the second major category in which "final intention" is problematical—those instances in which there is literally no final intention, either because the author never prepared his manuscript for publication or because he wavered in his revisions for successive printings.[62] Perhaps the most
A similar situation exists in connection with journals, notebooks, and other personal papers, except that for these classes of material
When writers leave unfinished, or unprepared for publication, literary works of other genres—those which are normally circulated in published form—the problem is somewhat different. In these cases the rejected readings, false starts, and uncanceled variants are of interest in showing the writer's manner of working and stylistic development, just as they are when found in the surviving manuscripts of a published work; but they do not reflect the essential nature of the work itself, as they do in a letter or a journal. An editor who completes the author's job by preparing such works for conventional publication (correcting errors, choosing among uncanceled variants, and the like) is not obscuring the final effect or meaning of the work but rather clarifying it. When a poem, left in manuscript, is posthumously published in the form of an exact transcript, it is being treated like a historical
The poems of Emily Dickinson present a special situation: they are clearly poems (not journal entries or letters), but they were not intended for publication. They contain both eccentric punctuation (often impossible to reproduce in type) and uncanceled alternative readings. If an editor decides to publish as exact transcriptions as possible of these poems (or even photographs of the manuscripts), he is doing what normally is most sensible for works not intended for publication. But in this case he would be doing less than full justice to the material, which belongs to a genre conventionally circulated in some kind of published form and with decisions among alternative readings already made. The fact that Emily Dickinson did not "intend" publication does not alter the basic nature of the material and automatically convert into notebook jottings what would have been called poetry if published. Her distrust of publication does not obligate an editor to leave her poems unpublished (or to edit them as if they were private papers) any more than an author's "deathbed" edition obligates an editor to regard previous editions as superseded. In either case the work has an existence distinct from the wishes (expressed or implied) of its creator, and "intention" regarding publication is different from the active intention embodied in the work. Whether or not Emily Dickinson's manuscripts were specifically "intended" for publication is really beside the point; the important matter is that they are manuscripts of poems not prepared for publication. Although an editor will rightly feel an obligation to present as fully as possible the evidence available in those manuscripts (as documents in the history of American literature), he should feel equally obliged to make decisions among the author's alternative readings and produce a clear text of the poems (as literature).[66] An editor who
IV
Some of the implications of the Dickinson problem for editorial theory are discussed by R. W. Franklin at the end of his important book The Editing of Emily Dickinson: A Reconsideration (1967). Franklin correctly asserts that "from the variant fair copies of a single poem we should choose its best" (p. 133), and he objects to any nonliterary or mechanical basis of selection among alternatives in unfinished manuscripts as resulting merely in "a worksheet without all the work" (p. 134). Since an uncompleted manuscript obviously lacks finality, he concludes, "The principle of editing that a text exactly represent the author's intention is inadequate." He therefore calls for "a new editorial procedure for material unprepared by the author for publication"—a procedure which would be "a compromise between the demands of authorial intention and the demands of the poems" (pp. 142-143). One might carry the argument a step further, however, and note that since authorial intention is ultimately ascertainable only through the poems, no compromise is necessary except in the sense that two kinds of edition, rather than a single one, may be desirable: a complete transcription, faithful to the demands of the document, and a reading text (or more than one), faithful to the demands of the work of art.
Generalizing upon the specific situation, Franklin points to the "conflicting bases of criticism and editing"—conflicting because the modern critical position upholds "criticism divorced from authorial intention." Is there an inconsistency, he is asking, within the discipline of literary study, if a text, presented to the literary critic for analysis in the light of one set of principles, is prepared for him by the editor under a different set of principles? An author's final intention, he believes,
Two issues are involved in these considerations, and they are basic to all kinds of editing, whether the copy-text is an uncompleted manuscript or a printed edition: (1) What does "intention" signify, and when is it final? (2) Does it matter whether the author's wording is recovered, particularly when emendations by others are improvements? These questions ask for definitions of the three words "final authorial intention" and for justification of them as an expression of the goal of editing. I hope that what I have said up to now has provided some answers to them and will serve as background for the following brief replies, specifically directed at Franklin's conclusions.
The second of the questions is easier to answer than the first. No one presumably would deny that any alteration in a literary work could be regarded as producing a different work and that the new work could be made the subject of critical analysis. Neither would anyone deny that nonauthorial revisions could produce a work superior to the original and more rewarding for study.[67] Nevertheless, if an editor sets out to edit the works of a particular writer, he has undertaken
The other question—the meaning of "intention"—is too complicated a philosophical issue to be settled here; but we can at least agree that authorial intention in literature cannot simply be equated with an explicit statement by the author explaining his motives, purposes, aims, wishes, or meaning, for intention must surely exist even if no such statements were made or are extant, and any available statements may be inadequate or misleading. The only direct evidence one has for what was in the author's mind is not what he says was there but what one finds in his work. An editor, only through his analysis and understanding of the meaning of the work in the light of his knowledge of the author and the times, will be in a position to use authorial active intention as a basis for editorial choice. That is to say, of the meanings which the editor sees in the work, he will determine, through a weighing of all the information at his command, the one which he regards as most likely to have been the author's; and that determination will influence his decisions regarding variant readings. Recognizing "finality" of intention, in turn, depends on his ability to distinguish revisions which develop an intention in the same direction from those which push it in another direction: the former represent final intentions, the latter new intentions. Whether the editor rejects such "new" intentions or edits a separate text embodying them will vary with the particular situation. But so long as he is producing an edition of an author's writings, he must choose among the author's uncanceled
If it is objected that this conception of the editorial process gives an editor excessive freedom and substitutes subjectivism for rigorous discipline, two answers may be made. In the first place, a scholarly editor (as opposed to a creative one) is still pledged to print only the author's words. He may select readings on the basis of his own literary judgment only when the alternatives are authorial variants; when he chooses an authorial reading previous to the author's last one (or what he judges to be the last one), his justification is that the reading is "final" in terms of his view of the work as an organic whole and that the later reading either creates a new work or is an isolated alteration at odds with the spirit of the work. Beyond that, one may observe that critical perception is necessarily crucial to any act of historical reconstruction, any evaluation of evidence, and thus any edition labeled "critical"; therefore, as Greg says, "it would be disastrous to curb the liberty of competent editors in the hope of preventing fools from behaving after their kind." Perhaps the principal source of difficulty lies in thinking of the editorial and the critical functions as essentially distinct. When one recognizes that justice can be done to an author only by doing justice to his text, one also understands that the editor and the critic must be inseparable.
Notes
An earlier version of this essay was written in the spring of 1968 for the first volume of Bibliographia, a journal then proposed for publication by Oliver & Boyd of Edinburgh. The plans for that journal have now been canceled by Oliver & Boyd, who have ceased the publication of works of this nature; and I am publishing the essay here, considerably revised. I mention this background only because I have alluded in print to an article with this title as "forthcoming in Bibliographia"; such citations should now be taken to refer to the article printed here.
SB, 3 (1950-51), 19-36; reprinted, with a few revisions, in Greg's Collected Papers, ed. J. C. Maxwell (1966), pp. 374-391. Cf. Fredson Bowers, "Current Theories of Copy-Text," Modern Philology, 48 (1950-51), 12-20; and "McKerrow's Editorial Principles for Shakespeare Reconsidered," Shakespeare Quarterly, 6 (1955), 309-324. For a detailed examination of Greg's position and of the commentators upon it, see G. T. Tanselle, "Greg's Theory of Copy-Text and the Editing of American Literature," SB, 28 (1975), 167-229. The Center for Editions of American Authors of the Modern Language Association of America has published a manual based on Greg's approach, Statement of Editorial Principles and Procedures (rev. ed., 1972); an appended essay, "Relevant Textual Scholarship," pp. 17-25, conveniently draws together references to many of the discussions of Greg's theory or of editions based on it.
"Textual Criticism," in The Aims and Methods of Scholarship in Modern Languages and Literatures, ed. James Thorpe (rev. ed., 1970), p. 33. Cf. his Textual and Literary Criticism (1959), p. 120: a critical edition attempts "to approach as nearly as may be to the ideal of the authorial fair copy."
"Some Principles for Scholarly Editions of Nineteenth-Century American Authors," SB, 17 (1964), 227.
I have made further comments on the role of judgment in editing in "Textual Study and Literary Judgment," PBSA, 65 (1971), 109-122.
It is convenient to use the word "author" in such statements as this. But nothing said here or elsewhere in this essay is meant to imply that scholarly editing is not also appropriate for anonymous works or works which are the product of an oral tradition. One can infer an "author" who created a given work even if a particular name is not attached to him or if "author" has to be defined as encompassing a number of people; in such cases, it is still meaningful to set as a goal the historical reconstruction of the text which reflects the intention (as defined below) of its creator(s) at a particular time. Cf. note 68 below.
Sometimes the literary effectiveness of a variant reading is used as an argument that the revision is authorial; but it is fallacious to assume that an author's revisions will always result in improvements (as judged by the editor or present-day scholars) and that no one else was capable of making such improvements.
Many of the general philosophical discussions do not take up the specific case of intention in literature (or in art generally), but such discussions may nevertheless provide some useful background by showing ways of approaching the subject. Two well-known works of this kind are G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (1957; 2nd ed., 1963); and Jack W. Meiland, The Nature of Intention (1970), which includes a checklist of related studies on pp. 131-134. A general treatment of the theoretical basis for connecting intention and art is provided in Anthony Savile's "The Place of Intention in the Concept of Art," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 69 (1968-69), 101-124.
Sewanee Review, 54 (1946), 468-488; reprinted in Wimsatt's The Verbal Icon (1954), pp. 3-18. They first set forth their position in the article on "Intention" in Dictionary of World Literature, ed. Joseph T. Shipley (1943), pp. 326-329; the criticism of this article by Ananda K. Coomaraswamy in "Intention," American Bookman, 1, no. 1 (Winter 1944), 41-48, was in part responsible for their elaborating their argument in the now famous essay. Since that time, each has restated and offered further comments upon the position. Beardsley began his Aesthetics (1958) with a section on "The Artist's Intention," pp. 17-29, 66-69; and more recently he has published The Possibility of Criticism (1970). And Wimsatt has made a "reentry into the debate" with "Genesis: A Fallacy Revisited," in The Disciplines of Criticism, ed. Peter Demetz, Thomas Greene, and Lowry Nelson, Jr. (1968), pp. 193-225. A great many discussions of the Wimsatt-Beardsley view have been published. Among the adverse criticisms, valuable essays are Eliseo Vivas's review of Verbal Icon, "Mr. Wimsatt on the Theory of Literature," Comparative Literature, 7 (1955), 344-361; William H. Capitan's examination of Beardsley's Aesthetics, "The Artist's Intention," Revue internationale de philosophie, 18 (1964), 323-334; and Michael Hancher's review of The Possibility of Criticism in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism [JAAC], 30 (1971-72), 391-394. Leslie Fiedler's "Archetype and Signature: A Study of the Relationship between Biography and Poetry," Sewanee Review, 60 (1952), 253-273, which takes a view opposed to Wimsatt and Beardsley, led to the discussion of both essays by Emilio Roma III, "The Scope of the Intentional Fallacy," Monist, 50 (1966), 250-266; and Frank Cioffi's "Intention and Interpretation in Criticism," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 64 (1963-64) 84-106, brought a rejoinder from Beardsley in a review in JAAC, 26 (1967-68), 144-146. Generally favorable responses are R. Jack Smith, "Intention in an Organic Theory of Poetry," Sewanee Review, 56 (1948), 625-633; and Rosemarie Maier, "'The Intentional Fallacy' and the Logic of Literary Criticism," College English, 32 (1970-71), 135-145 (with comments by Michael Hancher and Maier in the following volume, pp. 343-348).
Hirsch's argument had earlier appeared in "Objective Interpretation," PMLA, 75 (1960), 463-479, an essay included as an appendix in his book, pp. 209-244. The book, as an important and thoughtful statement of a position which has been unpopular since the advent of the New Criticism, has naturally been the subject of a great deal of discussion. Among the important reviews of the book are those by George Dickie, JAAC, 26 (1967-68), 550-552, and Robert Scholes, Philological Quarterly, 47 (1968), 280-283. The July 1968 number of Genre (1: 169-255) was devoted to "A Symposium" on the book, with contributions by Monroe C. Beardsley, George Dickie, Morse Peckham, Gale H. Carrithers, Jr., Leo Rockas, Arthur Efron, Merle E. Brown, and John Huntley. The following March Hirsch replied with "The Norms of Interpretation—A Brief Response," Genre, 2 (1969), 57-62; and he has recently offered a further elaboration of some of his ideas in "Three Dimensions of Hermeneutics," New Literary History, 3 (1971-72), 245-261. Morse Peckham discusses both the Wimsatt-Beardsley essay and Hirsch's book in "The Intentional? Fallacy?", New Orleans Review, 1 (1968-69), 116-124, reprinted in The Triumph of Romanticism (1970), pp. 421-444.
For instance, Wimsatt, recognizing that the contents of a work may be used to learn something about the author, says, "For whatever does get into a poem presumably is put there by the poet and reflects something in the poet's personality and life" ("Genesis: A Fallacy Revisited," p. 199). But the role of the editor is precisely to try to remove that "presumably" and to present a text consisting of what was in fact put there by the author. Similarly, Marcia Muelder Eaton, in "Good and Correct Interpretations of Literature," JAAC, 29 (1970-71), 227-233, remarks, "For purposes of simplicity I am assuming that the speaker uttered the words he meant to utter, i.e., that there were no slips of the tongue. This is certainly not too much to assume, since our main interest here is literature, and we certainly make such assumptions with respect to literary works" (p. 230). But slips of the author's pen or the compositor's hand, not later caught by the author, are the equivalent of "slips of the tongue" and certainly do occur in printed matter.
Throughout this essay I use "critical" in the common sense of "entailing judgment"—the sense which the word carries in the term "critical edition." I am not, that is to say, using "criticism" in the special sense which Hirsch (Validity in Interpretation, pp. 210-211) gives to it in his distinction between "interpretation" and "criticism," where the first means "the construction of textual meaning as such" ("the meaning of the text") and the second "builds on the results of interpretation," confronting "textual meaning not as such, but as a component within a larger context" ("the significance of the text"). I do not discuss here (except briefly near the end of section III) editions which are not critical—editions, that is, which present exact transcriptions of particular texts and which do not involve the editor's judgment in emending those texts.
This view is expressed by Rosemarie Maier (see note 8 above): "it is extremely unlikely that the determination of a text to criticize is actually literary criticism; textual decisions, unless they are the result of criticism of each version as an individual poem, are actually pre-critical decisions" (p. 144).
This influential treatment of meaning (edited by J. O. Urmson from Austin's notes for the 1955 William James Lectures) provides a useful terminology for discussing speech acts. A "locutionary" act involves only the "performance of an act of saying something"; an "illocutionary" act involves the "performance of an act in saying something" (p. 99); and a "perlocutionary" act involves "what we bring about or achieve by saying something" (p. 109). Another important account of meaning, taking an intentionalist approach (based on the idea that language consists of "nonnatural" signs which are given an "occasion-meaning" by a speaker), is H. P. Grice's "Meaning," Philosophical Review, 66 (1957), 377-388, supplemented by his "Utterer's Meaning and Intentions," Philosophical Review, 78 (1969), 147-177. There have been a considerable number of papers which build upon or analyze Austin's and Grice's contributions. Austin has been used by, among others, William P. Alston in Philosophy of Language (1964), esp. pp. 34-49 (cf. his "Linguistic Acts," American Philosophical Quarterly, 1 [1964], 138-146), and John R. Searle in Speech Acts (1969), esp. pp. 54-71; and Michael Hancher has illustrated the usefulness of the concept of illocutionary acts in analyzing literature in "Understanding Poetic Speech Acts," College English, 36 (1974-75), 632-639. A "largely destructive criticism" of Grice which is of particular interest to students of literature is Max Black's "Meaning and Intention: An Examination of Grice's Views," New Literary History, 4 (1972-73), 257-279 (which also contains a listing of many of the previous commentaries on Grice). Marcia Eaton has contributed a checklist of material on speech-act theory to Centrum, 2, no. 2 (Fall 1974).
The essays referred to are Gang, "Intention," Essays in Criticism, 7 (1957), 175-186; Kemp, "The Work of Art and the Artist's Intentions," British Journal of Aesthetics, 4 (1964), 146-154; Peckham, "Reflections on the Foundations of Modern Textual Editing," Proof, 1 (1971), 122-155 (see p. 152; Peckham discusses these matters at greater length, but does not use these particular terms, in "The Intentional? Fallacy?", cited in note 9 above); Skinner, "Motives, Intentions and the Interpretation of Texts," New Literary History, 3 (1971-72), 393-408. See also Richard Kuhns, "Criticism and the Problem of Intention," Journal of Philosophy, 57 (1960), 5-23, which distinguishes "intention as aiming at a result" from "intention as the conveying of a meaning." George Whalley prefers to use the term "intension" (which he defines as "the impulsive orientation of the person [author] in a moment of awareness"), because "intention" implies "a disguised attempt to explain the contemplative in terms of the technical" (Poetic Process [1953], p. xxvii).
Active intention thus corresponds to Austin's illocutionary act and to most of the locutionary act (Hancher, pp. 841-842).
His emphasis on "the" in several key statements (e.g., p. 851) implies that other definitions of meaning are possible; indeed, he goes on to make explicit the point that "we may entertain other meanings that seem valuable."
Richard Ohmann has attempted to draw such a line in "Speech Acts and the Definition of Literature," Philosophy and Rhetoric, 4 (1971), 1-19; and "Speech, Literature, and the Space Between," New Literary History, 4 (1972-73), 47-63. His definition of a literary work is "a discourse whose sentences lack the illocutionary forces that would normally attach to them. Its illocutionary force is mimetic" (1971, p. 14). He insists that his dividing line is a firm one, but the result is that some utterances not usually regarded as literature (jokes, "ironic rejoinders," "fables within political speeches") fall on the literature side. "Let me simply record my belief," he replies, "that the definition is not severely at fault in admitting the wrong discourses to the category of literature" (p. 16). Cf. his earlier "Speech, Action, and Style," in Literary Style: A Symposium, ed. Seymour Chatman (1971), pp. 241-259: "literature can be accurately defined as discourse in which the seeming acts are hypothetical" (p. 254). Beardsley takes a similar approach but seems to concede that his dividing line is more suggestive than precise. Literature, he says, is characterized by "its exploitation to a high degree of the illocutionary-act potential of its verbal ingredients"; it is "the complex imitation of a compound illocutionary act" (The Possibility of Criticism, p. 61). But he admits that what this amounts to is that a literary work has "richness and complexity of meaning"—or, earlier, that it "directs attention to itself as an object of rewarding scrutiny" (p. 60). More recently he has refined his definition, partly in response to Colin A. Lyas, who (in "The Semantic Definition of Literature," Journal of Philosophy, 66 [1969], 81-95) had criticized his previous definition of literature (Aesthetics, pp. 126-128) as "a discourse in which an important part of the meaning is implicit." Beardsley now defines "literary discourse" as "discourse that is either an imitation illocutionary act or distinctly above the norm in its ratio of implicit to explicit meaning" (both help to make a discourse "an object of attention in its own right")—see pp. 37-38 of "The Concept of Literature," in Literary Theory and Structure: Essays in Honor of William K. Wimsatt, ed. Frank Brady, John Palmer, and Martin Price (1973), pp. 23-39. This kind of definition, it seems to me, does not solve the problem but only shifts the terms in which it is expressed: one still has the problem of distinguishing between real illocutionary acts and imitations of illocutionary acts. Moreover, Marcia Muelder Eaton has shown that the author's intention has just as direct a bearing on such imitations of illocutionary acts as on illocutionary acts themselves; she proposes (in an extension of Austin's terminology) that these imitations be called "translocutionary" acts. See "Art, Artifacts, and Intentions," American Philosophical Quarterly, 6 (1969), 165-169; and "Good and Correct Interpretations of Literature" (see note 10 above). E. D. Hirsch, in "Some Aims of Criticism" (in the Wimsatt festschrift, pp. 41-62), argues that literature has "no independent essence": "It is an arbitrary classification of linguistic works which do not exhibit common distinctive traits, and which cannot be defined as an Aristotelian species. . . . The idea of literature is not an essentialistic idea" (p. 52). Cf. also College English, 36 (1974-75), 453.
As Quentin Skinner puts it, "an understanding of conventions, however implicit, must remain a necessary condition for an understanding of all types of speech act." See p. 135 of his "Conventions and the Understanding of Speech Acts," Philosophical Quarterly, 20 (1970), 118-138. He later (in the article cited in note 14 above) makes a focus on conventions one of his two rules (along with focus on "the writer's mental world") for recovering intention (pp. 406-407). The role of conventions in understanding is one of the concerns of Karl Aschenbrenner, in "Intention and Understanding," University of California Publications in Philosophy, 25 (1950), 229-270. Saussure's distinction between "langue" and "parole," summarized by Hirsch in Validity in Interpretation, pp. 231-235 (cf. pp. 69-71, leading into his discussion of "genre"), offers an approach to the relation between the "system of linguistic possibilities" which a language provides ("langue") and an individual utterance made in that language ("parole"). Theories of language are discussed by Morris Weitz in connection with multiple interpretations of a literary work in Hamlet and the Philosophy of Literary Criticism (1964), pp. 215-227. See also P. F. Strawson, "Intention and Convention in Speech Acts," Philosophical Review, 73 (1964), 439-460, and other discussions of Grice alluded to in note 13 above.
Geoffrey Payzant expresses this idea in broader terms: "Of the shapes that are imposed through skill upon stuff . . . some are devised by the maker and some are not." See p. 157 of "Intention and the Achievement of the Artist," Dialogue, 3 (1964-65), 153-159.
"The Intentional? Fallacy?" (see note 9 above), p. 441. Cf. Sidney Gendin, "The Artist's Intentions," JAAC, 23 (1964-65), 193-196: "We do expect, much of the time, that authorship or discovery will carry with it expert knowledge. But in such cases it is the knowledge itself which becomes the ground for being the authority; the authorship is not the ground. . . . If an artist has some peculiar knowledge of his work, it is not obvious that this is so merely because he is its creator. We must have some independent means of establishing his expertness" (p. 194). René Wellek says that an author's statements "might not even represent an accurate commentary on his work, and at their best are not more than such a commentary," in his and Austin Warren's Theory of Literature (2nd ed., 1956), p. 137.
"Motives, Intentions . . ." (see note 14 above), p. 405. Of course, authors' statements may be deliberately deceiving rather than "self-deceiving." Beardsley points out that artists "are often inclined to the most whimsical and bizarre statements [about their work], and seem to enjoy being deliberately misleading"; see p. 292 of his "On the Creation of Art," JAAC, 23 (1964-65), 291-304.
Such as that supporting the idea offered by Beardsley in The Possibility of Criticism, pp. 16-37; or those opposing it presented by Hirsch in Validity in Interpretation, pp. 10-14, by Peckham in "The Intentional? Fallacy?" (see note 9 above), and by Hancher in "Three Kinds of Intention" (see note 15 above).
Coomaraswamy (see note 8 above) makes a similar point: "one can so identify oneself with a subject and point of view that one can foresee what will be said next. . . . If, in fact, one cannot do this, textual emendation would be possible only on grammatical or metrical grounds" (p. 46). Isabel C. Hungerland, too, comments on this matter: "The way in which we interpret (explain and see) a whole literary work may determine our understanding of words (e.g., where there are ambiguous words), of sentences (e.g., where ironic meanings are possible), or allusions"; see p. 742 of "The Concept of Intention in Art Criticism," Journal of Philosophy, 52 (1955), 733-742. Hans Zeller, in "A New Approach to the Critical Constitution of Literary Texts," SB, 28 (1975), 231-264, takes the "predictability" of a text as an argument against the use of the text as a key to its author's intention: "To edit the text according to the intention of the author, when the singularities of his intention are known to us only through this text, can be achieved only if the text is in a certain sense redundant, that is to say, predictable. But this condition is fulfilled, as experiments have shown, only in the case of utilitarian texts (e.g., newspaper articles), and not in the case of poetic texts" (p. 259). But this position surely takes "predictability" in too narrow a sense: the fact that "artistic structures . . . themselves transgress the rules or codes which they have set up in the text" does not mean that the critical editor is prevented from seeing when such a transgression is taking place.
Henry David Aiken puts the matter this way: "The aesthetic relevance of a particular interpretation . . . can be established only with respect to a certain mode of appreciation, a certain way of approaching and handling the work of art." See p. 748 of "The Aesthetic Relevance of Artists' Intentions," Journal of Philosophy, 52 (1955), 742-753.
Hirsch admits, "The text sometimes seems so much better if we ignore the author's probable intention or what he probably wrote. Every interpreter has a touch of the medieval commentator looking for the best meaning, and every editor has a drop of Bentley's blood. It is not rare that anachronistic meaning on some ground or other is undoubtedly the best meaning" ("Three Dimensions of Hermeneutics" [see note 9 above], p. 259).
As Cioffi (see note 8 above) says, "biographical facts act as a kind of sieve which exclude certain possibilities" (p. 90); "They can serve the eliminative function of showing that certain interpretations of a work are based on mistaken beliefs about the author's state of knowledge" (p. 92). Similarly, Huw Morris Jones, in "The Relevance of the Artist's Intentions," British Journal of Aesthetics, 4 (1964), 138-145, comments, "We can eliminate some interpretations as being such that an artist at a certain period in a certain society could never have intended such meanings" (p. 140).
"The Science of Interpretation and the Art of Interpretation," Modern Language Notes, 85 (1970), 791-802. The first, he says, involves questions of validity, the second questions of value. A similar distinction is made by Eaton in "Good and Correct Interpretations of Literature" (see note 10 above).
"Intention" (see note 14 above), pp. 184-186. Hirsch's principal discussion of "Unconscious and Symptomatic Meanings," on pp. 51-57 of Validity in Interpretation, tries to distinguish between those unconscious meanings that are "coherent with the consciously willed type which defines the meaning as a whole" (p. 54) and those that are "symptomatic" of the author's personality, attitudes, and the like. The latter, while interesting and even important, are not part of the "verbal meaning" of a work, whereas the former are a part of it, since they are locatable in a specific "linguistic sign." This dichotomy is of course an application of Hirsch's larger distinction between meaning and significance, but it also serves to illustrate that one cannot escape the primacy of the text itself as a guide to intended meaning. Some criticism of this part of Hirsch's discussion occurs in Beardsley's The Possibility of Criticism, pp. 20-21.
Theodore Redpath is making roughly the same point when he says that "the probable intention of the poet does at least sometimes afford a criterion by which to judge whether a certain meaning which is attributed to a poem is probably correct or not." See p. 366 of "Some Problems of Modern Aesthetics," in British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, ed. C. A. Mace (1957), pp. 361-390. In other words, the primary emphasis is on what one finds in the poem; one can then try to determine whether it is a possible, and even a probable, meaning for the author, given the circumstances he was in at the time, to have intended. Similarly, Savile (see note 7 above) remarks, "At least in the context of art we know that the temporal and geographical point of origin of the text, the documents accessible to the artist, and the cultural climate of his time are all of first importance in assessing what interpretation of his text is the best in the circumstances of its production. . . . With the aid of hindsight we may get closer to the best possible contemporary reading than any contemporary did. We may be helped in this by later works, or by theories of behaviour that make explicit to us what the artist only dimly intuited" (pp. 122-123).
Ray Lewis White's edition (1968), though it is called a "critical text," fails to make these decisions, for it includes in brackets in the text both the passages marked for deletion on the typescript and the further passages deleted in the printed text. I have commented on the shortcomings of this volume and the other volumes in this edition in "The Case Western Reserve Edition of Sherwood Anderson: A Review Article," Proof, 4 (1974), 183-209.
See Walter B. Rideout's review of White's edition of A Story Teller's Story in English Language Notes, 7 (1969-70), 70-73.
For further details, see The Rise of Silas Lapham, ed. Walter J. Meserve and David J. Nordloh (Selected Edition of William Dean Howells, 1971), pp. 373-388.
The relationship between the readings of the American and English editions is explored in detail in the "Note on the Text" to the forthcoming Moby-Dick volume in the Northwestern-Newberry Edition of The Writings of Herman Melville.
"Textual Introduction," in Miscellanies by Henry Fielding, Esq; Volume One, ed. Henry Knight Miller (Wesleyan Edition, 1972), pp. lii-liii.
Most of these techniques of bibliographical analysis are conveniently illustrated in Charlton Hinman's The Printing and Proof-Reading of the First Folio of Shakespeare (1963); the principles underlying the use of the techniques are explored in Fredson Bowers's Bibliography and Textual Criticism (1964).
This example is discussed by Fredson Bowers in his edition of Crane's Tales of Adventure (University of Virginia Edition of The Works of Stephen Crane, 1970), p. 198. He takes up the general problem of "radiating texts"—the situation in which two or more extant texts are equally close to the lost manuscript, with no intervening texts surviving—in "Multiple Authority: New Problems and Concepts of Copy-Text," Library, 5th ser., 27 (1972), 81-115.
Anderson's editor, Ray Lewis White, seems to take both sides of the question. In his edition of Tar (1969), he says that "Anderson's loose punctuation, meant to reproduce for the reader a flowing, simple style, was standardized and 'stiffened' by the Boni and Liveright editors" (p. xvii); in Marching Men (1972), he reports that Anderson "learned to apologize for his untutored prose" and "continued all his life entrusting to his publishers final preparation of his writing" (pp. xxiv-xxv). Cf. note 33 above. For the view of a publisher's editor, defending publishing-house alterations as part of an author's intention, see Albert Erskine, "Authors and Editors: William Faulkner at Random House," in The William Faulkner Collection at West Point and the Faulkner Concordances, ed. Jack L. Capps (1974), pp. 14-19. Simon Nowell-Smith has provided a survey of author-publisher relations in respect both to punctuation and to censorship in "Authors, Editors, and Publishers," in Editor, Author, and Publisher, ed. William J. Howard (1969), esp. pp. 8-16.
Principles of Textual Criticism (1972), p. 165. Paul Baender similarly believes that the Center for Editions of American Authors (following Greg's principles) "has not sufficiently recognized that a writer's acquiescence in his publisher's alterations may also be construed as self-expression"; see p. 141 of "Reflections upon the CEAA by a Departing Editor," Resources for American Literary Study, 4 (1974), 131-144. Zeller (see note 26 above) goes farther and says that whatever an author passes in preparing the copy for an edition (with the exception of a strictly defined category of "faults") should be regarded as authorized, regardless of its source, for the author in passing it is reacting to a different version of his work in which it plays a role: "it does not matter whether the variants are original or extraneous, misprints (as we shall see, there are misprints and misprints) or variants introduced by a publisher's editor. . . . The necessary condition for our establishment of text is only that he [the author] should have registered the readings in question" (p. 256). Examining the author's motivation in passing certain readings which did not originate with him is futile, Zeller argues, because "the magnetic needle of the author's wishes is quivering in the field of non-aesthetic forces" (p. 245; see also note 52 below).
I have offered a more detailed and direct criticism of Thorpe's and Gaskell's position in SB, 28 (1975), 222-227.
The Waste Land: A Facsimile and Transcript of the Original Drafts Including the Annotations of Ezra Pound, ed. Valerie Eliot (1971), p. xxxii.
One must use such qualifiers as "in effect" when calling this kind of version a "new work," since obviously there must be something similar about the two versions or they would not be regarded as "versions of a work" in the first place. At the same time, there is the implication that not every difference produces, for the practical purposes of editing, a "new work." Cf. note 54 below.
Bowers, in his essay "Textual Criticism" in the Thorpe pamphlet (see note 2 above), briefly refers to such cases in which "the rewriting is so extensive as to make ridiculous any attempt at synthesis of the two forms in one critical text" (p. 47; see also his footnote 32).
Of course, a revision which does not actually implement the aim of, say, simplification may have been made by the author in the belief that it does. It may be impossible for an editor to distinguish between such revisions and those which genuinely were unconnected with the motive of simplification. All he can do is to judge, on the basis of the texts in front of him and his knowledge of the author, which revisions the author can reasonably be thought to have considered simplifications (whether or not they seem such to the editor himself).
For a more detailed discussion of these revisions and the editorial problems they pose, see Typee, ed. Harrison Hayford, Hershel Parker, and G. Thomas Tanselle (Northwestern-Newberry Edition, 1968), pp. 288-291, 315-318.
Whether or not one might wish to produce a separate text incorporating vertical revisions generally depends on how much historical or aesthetic interest such a text would have. In the case of revisions made because of outside pressure to expurgate, there would presumably be little interest in having a separately edited text of such a version.
Further examples of Melville's revisions of Typee, along with a discussion of the possibility of editorial rejection of authorial revisions in this and other works of Melville, are given by Hershel Parker in "Melville and the Concept of 'Author's Final Intentions,'" Proof, 1 (1971), 156-168.
Charles Vandersee, "James's 'Pandora': The Mixed Consequences of Revision," SB, 21 (1968), 93-108 (see p. 107). The same kind of comment can be made in regard to revisions in a lyric poem. Thomas Clayton, for instance, writing on "Some Versions, Texts, and Readings of 'To Althea, from Prison,'" in PBSA, 68 (1974), 225-235, says of two readings that "it is pointless to argue which is 'better'; the readings are different, and the versions of the poem are significantly different depending upon the presence of 'birds' or 'gods,' respectively: the dialectic of the whole depends upon the part" (p. 234).
Even a nonauthorial variant, of course, produces a separate work which could be made the subject of critical analysis, but the scholarly editor's aim, as it has been defined, is to reconstruct the text (or texts) in conformity with the author's intention. As to whether his aim should be so defined, see below in section IV. Zeller (see note 26 above) does hold the position that "a new version comes into existence through a single variant," because "a text, as text, does not in fact consist of elements but of the relationships between them" and therefore "variation at one point has an effect on invariant sections of the text" (p. 241). He believes that each authorized text has an integrity of its own and that the editor's duty is to intervene in a text only to correct "textual faults" (readings which contradict "the internal text structure" [p. 260] and which are confirmed as corrupt by bibliographical analysis). To judge variants individually and to emend one text with authorial variants from another is, in his view, to produce a "contaminated" text. Zeller has focused clearly on the problem, and certain parts of his discussion are similar to what I am saying here. The central difference between his position and the one I set forth below is that for him a "new version implies a new intention" (p. 241), whereas I believe that a critical distinction can be made between versions resulting from different intentions for the work as a whole and those resulting from the same intention. Furthermore, Zeller does not think that intention can be defined to exclude the nonliterary forces which affect authorial decisions: "What is termed the intention of the author is an undetachable part of these forces. . . . Only the textual history is within the editor's reach" (p. 244). But if it makes sense to speak of artistic and nonartistic elements in intention (that is, to speak of active intention and certain programmatic intentions), then there is surely a dividing line between them (however concealed) which critical intelligence can attempt to discover. Zeller's procedure does produce what can be called a critical text, because errors are corrected; but emendations of authorial variants are ruled out, and the issue finally becomes the question of the value of a critical approach to editing.
If they considered the variants singly rather than in groups, even a relatively small number of variants would result in an astronomical number of separate works; it is true, however, that any group of authorial revisions may contain some which seem to move in a different direction from the others and which thus demand separate consideration.
From here on I use "separate work"—as I trust the context indicates—in the practical sense of "a work to be edited separately."
Richard Kuhns (see note 14 above) is getting at this same question when he says, "Within limits changes can be made without altering the basic organization and fundamental meaning of the work; but if we go outside those limits the work is seriously affected. . . . There is a difference between the values of the parts of a work which if changed would not alter the over-all effect of the work, and the values of the elements of a work which if changed would alter the over-all effect of the work" (p. 18). The key, in his terms, is whether or not the "style" is affected, "style" being defined as "a kind of organization of elements capable of sustaining a constant 'focal effect.'"
For a fuller discussion of this document and its editorial implications, see Typee (cited in note 48 above), pp. 312-313.
I have discussed this case in connection with Greg's theory, on pp. 221-223 of "The New Editions of Hawthorne and Crane," Book Collector, 23 (1974), 214-229.
Bowers has made further comments on the relationships between editions offering "eclectic" texts and those offering texts of particular stages of revision, in "Remarks on Eclectic Texts," Proof, 4 (1974), 31-76.
Some of the earlier versions have been edited separately: see, for example, Whitman's Manuscripts: Leaves of Grass (1860), ed. Fredson Bowers (1955), which prints as parallel texts the manuscript versions of certain poems and their first published versions (in 1860); and Leaves of Grass: The First (1855) Edition, ed. Malcolm Cowley (1959). Cf. Bowers, "The Walt Whitman Manuscripts of 'Leaves of Grass' (1860)," in his Textual and Literary Criticism (1959), pp. 35-65.
As John Kemp (see note 14 above) says, "a published work of art has been, as it were, detached from the artist, and he has sent it out into the world, with the result that later versions do not necessarily cancel earlier published ones as later cancel earlier in the working-out stage before publication" (p. 152).
If finality is defined in terms of publication, one could say that the latter case involves multiple intentions. The whole pattern of revisions in such a case, however, separates it from the usual instances of continual revision and suggests that the author had not really come to a decision when he was forced to select one reading or the other for publication at a particular time.
For a fuller discussion of these problems (with somewhat different conclusions), see Robert Halsband, "Editing the Letters of Letter-Writers," SB, 11 (1958), 25-37; and Simon Nowell-Smith (see note 40 above), esp. pp. 16-27.
A good example of this method is the Harvard University Press edition of The Journals and Miscellaneous Notebooks of Ralph Waldo Emerson, ed. William H. Gilman et al. (1960- ). The volumes of detailed transcription currently in progress are to be followed by selections in clear text. Whenever a text is likely to be quoted or reprinted frequently in standard typographical contexts where symbols and multiple readings seem (by tradition) out of place, it becomes particularly important to provide such additional clear texts, despite the theoretical difficulties they entail. For a discussion of some of the problems of editing journals, see William H. Gilman, "How Should Journals Be Edited?", Early American Literature, 6 (1971), 73-83. Cf. also G. T. Tanselle, "Some Principles for Editorial Apparatus," SB, 25 (1972), 41-88 (esp. pp. 46-47); and Eleanor D. Kewer, "Case Histories in the Craft of the Publisher's Editor, Culminating in a Justification of Barbed Wire," in Editor, Author, and Publisher, ed. William J. Howard (1969), pp. 65-73.
E. A. J. Honigmann, in The Stability of Shakespeare's Text (1965), argues that Shakespeare perhaps made revisions in the process of copying, so that some of the variants we now have may represent authorial "second thoughts." The editor, therefore, must "screw his courage to the sticking place and choose between each pair of variants"; what he is doing is "to attempt a feat left undone by Shakespeare, to finalise an unfinalised text" (p. 168).
Thomas H. Johnson's Harvard edition of Emily Dickinson's poems (1955) presents a clear text, with variant readings in notes; but the decisions as to which readings were to be included in the main text were not generally made on the basis of literary judgment. Cf. Johnson's "Establishing a Text: The Emily Dickinson Papers," SB, 5 (1952-53), 21-32.
James Thorpe, however, does not seem to me to give adequate recognition to this possibility in the opening chapter ("The Aesthetics of Textual Criticism," originally published in PMLA, 80 [1965], 465-482) of his Principles of Textual Criticism (1972). He grants that "status as a work of art is not affected by whether [the work's] intentions all belong to the titular author"; but he immediately adds that "the integrity of the work of art depends very much on the work being limited to those intentions which are the author's," and he then insists that it is this "final integrity which should be the object of the critic's chief attention" (p. 31). Of course, his book is concerned with editing which seeks to establish what the author wrote; but the nature of that activity might have been more helpfully defined in relation to other possible editorial goals. Instead, there is the implication (which contradicts the first statement quoted above) that the work of art can only be preserved through the efforts of editors who purge it of the nonauthorial features that it continually attracts. We are told that "forces are always at work thwarting or modifying the author's intentions" and that the work "is thus always tending toward a collaborative status" (p. 48); therefore, "aesthetic objects . . . must be protected in order to preserve the work from becoming a collaborative enterprise" (p. 49). The scholarly editor is not so much "protecting" the work as restoring a particular form of it which has historical (and perhaps also aesthetic) interest; purely as an aesthetic object the work might well be better off without protection.
See A. Walton Litz, "Maxwell Perkins: The Editor as Critic," in Editor, Author, and Publisher, ed. William J. Howard (1969), pp. 96-112. The author's attitude toward such changes is of course a separate matter, taken up in section II above. Morse Peckham has questioned whether it is meaningful to think of the "author" as distinguishable from others who work on the same text, and thus whether the recovery of authorial intention is a possible goal, in "Reflections on the Foundations of Modern Textual Editing" (see note 14 above). Whenever an author revises his work, Peckham argues, he is looking at something already created and is no longer in the position of the creator (or the "initiator" of the "discourse"); he may be the first to revise the work, but his activity is no different from that of publishers' readers or editors who come along later. Peckham's point is similar to the one I am making here, because it recognizes that the activity of "editing" need not have any connection with a concept of "author." I would go on, however, as Peckham does not, and claim that the initiator of a discourse can be identified as a historical figure (whether or not his name is known —cf. note 5 above), distinct from others because he is the initiator; that an interest may attach to this initiator; and that the task of attempting to segregate his contributions to the discourse from those of others is therefore one legitimate scholarly pursuit. I have commented in somewhat more detail on this argument of Peckham's in SB, 28 (1975), 215-219. Cf. also the remark by Anthony Savile (see note 7 above): "If art conveys value through intentional means it is entirely natural that we should single out for attention the agent whose intentions these are" (p. 106). Zeller's position (see notes 26, 42, and 52 above) is similar to Peckham's in stressing "the difficulty, indeed the impossibility, of obtaining a text attributable exclusively to the author" (p. 249). But, unlike Peckham, he does not reach the point of questioning the individuality of the "author"; indeed, he distinguishes between the attitude of the author toward his text and the attitude of "the reader, the exegete or the editor" (p. 258). Baender (see note 42 above) also agrees with some parts of Peckham's discussion; but he is opposing Peckham when he affirms his belief "that human beings are discrete, that an individual has the power and privilege of self-expression and of changing his mind, and that other individuals do not have the privilege of altering that self-expression or of forcing that change of mind" (p. 141).
| ||