| ||
Editing without a Copy-Text
by
G. Thomas Tanselle
[*]
In the history of textual criticism, as of most human affairs, a few basic viewpoints have moved through the centuries in cyclical fashion, each losing favor temporarily in one area or another and then returning to prominence in an altered form. The fields concerned with reconstructing the past, like textual criticism, constantly reverberate with alternating claims about the place of judgment in the process. At one moment, objectivity seems possible, and artifacts tell their own stories with little or no assistance; at the next moment, subjectivity is welcomed, and artifacts are a springboard for the historical imagination. In the nineteenth century, for example, the genealogical approach to biblical and classical textual criticism, now associated with the name of Karl Lachmann, emerged from a desire to minimize the role of judgment in combining readings from variant texts and was thus a reaction to the less disciplined eclecticism of many eighteenth-century editors, who often altered texts according to their personal tastes. By the early twentieth century, in turn, there were efforts—as in the work of A. E. Housman—to reinstate an open acceptance of judgment. But even Housman's brilliant advocacy of the subjective element in textual criticism did not prevent several determined attempts in the twentieth century to develop mathematical procedures for weighing variants in ancient texts.
A distrust of subjectivity, in a different form from Lachmann's, came in the twentieth century to dominate the study of medieval writings: the procedure, which was anti-eclectic, involved selecting a "best text" and altering it only at the places that seemed obviously erroneous. Although, for post-medieval literature, the term "best text" has not been widely used, the term "copy-text" as employed by R. B. McKerrow in his 1904 edition of Thomas Nashe meant essentially the same thing. Thus the editing of Renaissance literature that proceeded alongside the "New Bibliography" emerged from this restrictive base—not unexpectedly,
One of the most revealing facts about his rationale, however, is—as the title of his paper suggests—its retention of a concept of "copy-text," a basic text into which alterations (or "emendations")[2] can be incorporated. It now seems time, after another half-century, to move beyond this often useful but nevertheless inherently restrictive concept. That Greg's intention was to liberate editorial judgment is indicated by his warning against "what may be called the tyranny of the copy-text"; but his recognition that a copy-text could indeed tyrannize did not cause him to abandon the concept. He was not quite ready to carry to its logical conclusion the dominant twentieth-century English line of thinking about the textual criticism of post-medieval literature, a line that had become gradually more liberal during the first half of the century—though the position he did take certainly constituted an important extension of it.
I
The first step in thinking through a new approach to the question of copy-text is to examine whether there is a future for critical editions—editions, that is, in which the editors, using their informed critical judgment, make alterations in the documentary forms of texts that have come down to us (or at least allow themselves the freedom to make such alterations, whether or not they ultimately find any changes to be necessary). All the various "best-text" or "copy-text" theories are concerned with the process of altering documentary texts; but if a convincing argument can be made that no such process is justified, then there is no point considering critical editing further. In the continual give-and-take of arguments over subjectivity and objectivity, some scholars naturally take the position that editions presenting critical texts are less valuable (if granted any value at all) than editions containing facsimile or diplomatic (or computer "hypertext") reproductions of texts as they appear in extant documents.[3] The late twentieth century has seen an energetic resurgence of this view, springing from two seemingly contradictory premises. One—that authors do not control either the language they use or the forces that allow their work to reach the public—denigrates the significance of authorial intention and thus brings renewed attention to texts as they were published. The other premise—that the process of revision and change through which verbal works move is of more valid concern than any single final text that may be postulated—causes increased interest to be directed toward the texts of every prepublication draft and revised edition. Although the former premise tends to reject the author and the
These trends have therefore publicized specific programmatic reasons for the production of facsimile and diplomatic editions, besides the obvious general motivation to make widely available the texts of unique manuscripts and scarce printed editions (recognizing, of course, that no photograph or transcription can preserve all the physical evidence of the original—and that all of it may be relevant to textual study).[5] Although facsimile and diplomatic editions are noncritical in that their editors' aim is to reproduce without alteration the words and punctuation of documentary texts, critical judgment is inevitably involved in deciphering handwritten (or poorly printed) texts and in deciding which documentary versions of a work to present (if all are not to be included). Because this decision-making is not intended to alter texts, however, the editions that result are usually thought of as more "objective," despite the number of subjective decisions that may have been involved; and although arguments about the relative amounts of subjectivity and objectivity in editing are normally concerned with critical editions, there is no doubt that those persons who wish to minimize subjectivity in critical editing should logically be drawn to noncritical editions. Facsimile and diplomatic editions, whatever subjectivity may underlie them, are fundamentally different in conception from editions in which the goal is to alter documentary texts according to some predetermined guideline. By not requiring such guidelines, they have seemed to need less discussion over the years than have critical editions; and their increased presence in recent methodological debates is to be welcomed as a partial redressing of the balance. There is no question that they serve an important function in the study of the past.
But any attempt to argue that they are necessarily superior to critical editions, or indeed that they constitute the only legitimate kind of edition, cannot possibly succeed. The two kinds must always coexist, for they represent two indispensable elements in approaching the past: the ordered presentation of artifactual evidence, and the creation, from that evidence, of versions of past moments that are intended to be more comprehensively faithful than the artifacts themselves—random (and perhaps damaged) survivors as they are. It is not possible, in any case, to prevent human beings from interpreting evidence; to ban critical editions would be as futile as to try to suppress any other product that reflects the natural
There is another reason that critical editions are essential: they are demanded by the very nature of verbal works. Like musical and choreographic works—and unlike works of visual and plastic art—verbal works employ an intangible medium. Any tangible representation of such a work—as in letterforms on paper—cannot be the work itself, just as choreographic notation or traditional musical scores are not works of dance or music. The media involved—language, movement, and sound—being intangible, these works can be stored only through conversion to another form, which in effect becomes a set of instructions for reconstituting the works.[7] Any instructions—indeed, any kind of reproduction or report—may be inaccurate, and thus every attempt to reconstruct such works (or versions of works) must include a readiness to recognize textual errors in their stored forms. Understanding the difference between works and documents also enables one to see that a concern with the integrity of discrete versions is not incompatible with the adoption of variants from different documents.[8] Reconstituting works (or versions) in intangible
II
Having established the necessity of critical editions, one can then consider what procedure should be followed in making the critical judgments they entail. Some kind of guideline is required if the operation is to be disciplined and historically oriented. Otherwise, textual decisions would simply reflect the editors' own preferences, and the results, which would not necessarily be without interest, would not be an attempt at historical reconstruction. Editorial taste is indeed essential, but an edited text should reflect, not the personal preferences of the editor, but the editor's judgments regarding the preferences of the author, or the author in conjunction with others, at a given moment. Simple as this distinction is, it has probably been the root of more textual disputes than any other single point. But since critical editing must rest on editorial judgment, a sufficient guideline would seem to be one that states the goal toward which that judgment is to be directed, perhaps indicating what ancillary information should be taken into account but without placing limits on the judgment itself: to say, for example, that an editor's literary sensitivity, informed by biographical, bibliographical, and more broadly
The fear that encouraging editorial judgment would amount to licensing personal preference, however, has repeatedly caused textual theorists to impose restrictions on the field within which editorial judgment is allowed to operate. The "best-text" theories are one result, and they have been curiously persistent, despite the ease with which their essential illogic can be exposed. In ruling that texts can be altered only where they are obviously incorrect, this approach seems to imply, incredibly, that texts are likely to be correct wherever they are not manifestly incorrect—a patent absurdity. A. E. Housman in 1903 pointed out this flaw most memorably, in the preface to the first volume of his edition of Manilius, and he wittily added, "assuredly there is no trade on earth, excepting textual criticism, in which the name of prudence would be given to that habit of mind which in ordinary human life is called credulity."[10] Perhaps the most basic way of stating the incoherence of the "best-text" approach is to observe that it begins with a belief that documentary texts can be improved through editorial intervention (otherwise there would be no reason to allow the correction of clearcut errors) but proceeds to cast doubt on the usefulness of such intervention (otherwise it would be allowed to operate more widely). If there were a chance that editorial judgment could correct a text at places not obviously incorrect, there would seem to be no reason not to sanction the effort; and one must therefore conclude, with Housman, that these places are assumed to be correct. Actually, however, there is no point looking for an explanation of this unreasoned approach other than a reflex reaction: the belief that a restriction of judgment was required to improve on the unscholarly eclecticism of the past.
McKerrow was undoubtedly caught up in this reaction when in 1904 he chose the second edition of Nashe's The Unfortunate Traveller as his copy-text, to be altered only at obviously erroneous points, on the grounds that it contained some revisions by the author (2: 197). He was not happy with all the readings that this policy forced him to retain, but he felt that he had "no choice" in the matter; when he stated that an editor could not "pick and choose among the variant readings of his author's works those which he himself would prefer in writings of his own," McKerrow did not admit the possibility that choice among variants could be performed on any other basis.[11] Thirty-five years later, in
Greg's primary purpose in "The Rationale of Copy-Text" was to provide a sound argument for greater editorial freedom of choice.[13] "I am only concerned," he unambiguously proclaimed, "to uphold his [the editor's] liberty of judgment" (p. 386); at another point he called it "disastrous" to "curb the liberty of competent editors" (p. 388). He asked why, if judgment was to be admitted in distinguishing possible from impossible readings (as it was in the "best-text" approaches), "should the choice between possible readings be withdrawn from its competence?" (p. 381). The judgment of an editor, he answered, "is likely to bring us closer to what the author wrote than the enforcement of an arbitrary rule." Curiously, however, Greg's strong endorsement of editorial freedom in regard to substantive variants was not extended to what he called "accidentals" (spelling and punctuation), for it was the function of the copy-text, in his view, to provide the accidentals. He made a clear distinction between the nearly automatic acceptance of copy-text accidentals and the use of judgment in dealing with substantives: "the copy-text should govern (generally) in the matter of accidentals,
It seems evident, nevertheless, that Greg was not entirely comfortable with the idea of restricting the role of judgment in any aspect of the editorial procedure. He inserted the word "generally" in his directive that "the copy-text should govern (generally) in the matter of accidentals"; and he insisted that the copy-text should not be "sacrosanct, even apart from the question of substantive variation," enumerating instances in which it is "within the discretion of an editor" to alter copy-text accidentals. He even went so far as to say that, in regard to "graphic peculiarities" (by which he meant some practices of spelling and punctuation), "the copy-text is only one among others" (pp. 385-386). If, therefore, copy-text accidentals may be altered whenever one believes there is good reason to do so, just as copy-text substantives may certainly be, the role of the copy-text turns out to be that of supplying readings (of both substantives and accidentals) whenever there seems no other basis for deciding. Greg would never have insisted that any reading should be retained simply because it was present in the copy-text, if an editor's informed judgment pointed to a different choice; such "tyranny of the copy-text" (p. 382)[14] was what he was striving to eliminate from textual criticism. Thus if one is to fall back on the copy-text (for accidentals as well as substantives) only when there is no other way to choose, the key element in his copy-text procedure is determining when two readings are in fact "exactly balanced" (p. 386)—or, to use the more famous term that he also employs, "completely indifferent" (p. 387). If, in an editor's
Greg himself was, however, somewhat tyrannized by the idea of copy-text, for his essay includes this statement: "whenever there is more than one substantive text of comparable authority, then although it will still be necessary to choose one of them as copy-text, and to follow it in accidentals, this copy-text can be allowed no over-riding or even preponderant authority as far as substantive readings are concerned" (pp. 384-385). Thus at the very moment when he emphasizes the necessity for freedom of editorial judgment in regard to substantive variants from documents of equal "extrinsic" (that is, genealogical) authority, he places a mechanical, unreasoned restriction on judgment applied to the accidentals. When the surviving texts of a work form an ancestral series and a copy-text is chosen for its position in the series, there is a justification for falling back on the copy-text when the variants seem indifferent. But when the documents do not form such a series, and when two of them seem evenly balanced in authority, there is no reason to give more weight to the accidentals in one; the fact that there is often little basis for making decisions about accidentals does not in such an instance justify assigning authority to the accidentals that happen to be in a single document. Greg criticized editors for "abdicating" the "editorial function" if in the case of substantives "of equal extrinsic authority" they relied "on some arbitrary canon, such as the authority of the copy-text" (p. 384). But he was giving them contrary advice for the accidentals.
It was after this passage, however, that he sanctioned the alteration of copy-text accidentals—presumably in both kinds of situations, both where texts can be ranked on genealogical grounds and where two or more authoritative texts appear unrankable. Thus the overriding point is the necessity for editorial judgment, which must operate regardless of the relationships among the documents; and the idea of a copy-text (feasible for ancestral series but meaningless for texts of equal authority,
III
The voluminous commentary engendered by Greg's essay has largely been concerned with the applicability of his approach beyond the field of Renaissance drama and with the appropriateness of concentrating on final authorial intention.[16] Most commentators have spent less time scrutinizing the general principles underlying Greg's recommendations than evaluating how useful those specific recommendations seem in different contexts, and thus there has been almost no questioning of the necessity for a concept of copy-text. The basic meaning of the term "copy-text" has remained stable from McKerrow's time onward—that is, the documentary text used as the basis for a scholarly edition. But the way in which a copy-text is selected and emended has undergone a remarkable shift during the twentieth century; and when the phrase "copy-text editing" is now used it signifies not what McKerrow would have understood by it but generally something close to what Greg meant by it. Being a critic of "copy-text editing" —and there have been many such critics in recent years—is likely to mean disapproving of the elevation of texts as completed by authors over texts as they emerged from publication or theatrical production, or objecting to the preference for the author's final intention rather than an earlier intention, or indeed decrying the practice of eclectic editing itself. But criticizing "copy-text editing" has not meant attacking the idea of copy-text. Whether or not editors of post-medieval writings have been successful in avoiding the "tyranny of the copy-text" as envisaged by Greg, they have not escaped the tyranny of the concept of copy-text.
Perhaps the most instructive example is Fredson Bowers, since he was the most prolific and influential editor of this century in the English-speaking scholarly world. He was also the person primarily responsible for the extension of Greg's ideas to the editing of post-Renaissance literature, and therefore one might think it unreasonable to expect that he would have been critical of "copy-text." Yet he was an ardent believer
The first of these essays, after sketching Greg's contribution[18] and some of Bowers's own applications of Greg's rationale to later literature, takes up instances of thoroughgoing authorial revision, a subject not dealt with by Greg in much detail. In such cases, Bowers says, when "the two texts are parallel enough for a comparison of the accidentals to be pertinent," an editor "can make some essay at treating the accidentals of the revised edition on the same critical basis as its substantives" (p. 462). What the editor must not do, Bowers insists, is "to succumb to the tyranny of the copy-text." If all variants—accidentals as well as substantives—are treated critically, Bowers recognizes that "in an ideal state" the editor "would arrive at compatible results without regard for the choice of copy-text" (pp. 462-463):
In the second essay, six years later, Bowers gives Greg's "Rationale" a more critical reading, examines its applicability to authorially revised editions of later periods (in the light of his own further experience), and finds that he has a "serious quarrel" with Greg's belief in "the lesser authority of a revised edition in cases of doubt" (p. 123). Although he is convinced that Greg's idea of choosing a copy-text for its accidentals is "still (and no doubt invariably) sound . . . for any period" (p. 147), he concludes that the greater accuracy of compositors in periods after the Renaissance means that indifferent substantive variants in revised editions of the last three centuries may generally be regarded as more likely to be authorial than compositorial (p. 155). There is an irony here in Bowers's partial return to McKerrow's belief in the whole body of substantive variants of a revised edition. Bowers's position is more flexible, but there is considerable similarity between McKerrow's idea of adopting all the variants when some are certainly authorial and Bowers's newly formed conviction of the likelihood "that an indifferent variant in the revised text is authorial" (p. 155). Bowers even admits the possibility that this view may apply to accidentals as well as substantives (depending on one's judgment of compositorial fidelity) and thus that the revised text could become the copy-text (p. 160). But given his recognition that
This reluctance is most dramatically revealed in his treatment of so-called "radiating texts"—texts that do not form an ancestral linear series but instead represent independent lines of descent from a common source. This kind of textual history is frequently encountered in the study of the manuscript traditions of ancient texts, but Bowers's attention was drawn to it by his editing of Stephen Crane, whose syndicated newspaper pieces provide a classically pure example of the problem: the various original newspaper texts of a piece are independently derived from (and equidistant from) the master copy supplied by the syndicate office to the subscribing newspapers. In the absence of such master copy, the syndicated appearances—"radiating" from the lost original—constitute the only evidence for reconstructing what the syndicate office sent out (which is, in turn, at least one step removed from Crane's lost manuscripts). In the fifth and sixth volumes of his Crane edition (Tales of Adventure and Tales of War, both 1970), Bowers first dealt with this situation extensively.[21]
His procedure, at points of variation in punctuation among the radiating texts, was generally to adopt the reading present in the largest number of them (though he recognized that not every instance could be handled on a quantitative basis); and then he selected as a copy-text the single newspaper text that contained the largest number of the readings that he had decided to adopt. As he says in discussing "The Pace of Youth," the first of the pieces in Tales of Adventure, the Dayton Daily Journal text "has been selected as copy-text for its general concurrence with majority opinion" (p. cxlii). This use of "copy-text" of course shifts the meaning of the term from what Greg (and Bowers in earlier discussions)
The conceptual imprecision in this shifting use of "copy-text" probably had little effect on Bowers's final text, since his copy-texts in these instances were chosen not for their authority but for the extent of their agreement with what he had already decided the text should contain. Nevertheless, the fuzziness surrounding "copy-text" here does have practical consequences for the reader, through its effect on the apparatus. Because the list of emendations provides a record of editorial alterations made in the designated copy-texts, and because the "historical collation" records only substantive variants, the variants in accidentals among the radiating texts are not fully reported. Bowers does say, in his headnote to the emendations list in both of these Crane volumes, "when as in syndicated newspaper versions a number of texts have equal claim to authority, all are noted in the Emendations listing" (5:211; 6:335). What this statement means is that a full record of variants in accidentals is normally[23] provided for each place where the designated copy-text is
Bowers's primary theoretical discussion of radiating texts occurs not in the Crane edition but in the latter half of his essay on "Multiple Authority," where it constitutes his principal supplement to Greg—since it, unlike most of his other treatments of copy-text, focuses on a situation that Greg did not attempt to cover. But his discussion, pioneering as it is in many ways, is weakened by his retention of the idea of a copy-text, especially after having in effect shown why it is irrelevant. He emphasizes, quite properly, the role of critical judgment, pointing out that for radiating texts it must be applied as fully to accidentals as to substantives.[24] A statistical approach, he rightly asserts, is not sufficient, for an unconventional authorial reading might be normalized by many compositors and "preserved only by the dogged or indifferent few"; "the minority reading may sometimes need to be adopted on critical grounds" (p. 468). This cogent reasoning implies the importance of recording all the variant readings in radiating texts; and it is therefore revealing of his divided mind that he proceeds to advocate choosing a copy-text "requiring the least amount of apparatus" (p. 471).[25]
He recognizes the reasons for dispensing with the concept of copy-text altogether in such situations: if there are eight radiating texts, he says, the copy-text is "only one of eight equal witnesses, of no greater presumptive authority than the other seven" (p. 470); the choice of copy-text, then, is "theoretically indifferent" and "largely a question of convenience"; it is made only after the critical text has already been constructed (p. 471), and it is "not integral to the editing" (p. 485). He is therefore receptive to the possibility of having no copy-text; yet he maintains that a copy-text be chosen "to serve as the physical basis" (p. 471) for a critically reconstructed text, without making clear why the "physical basis" must be equated with a single document, when in fact it is a group of documents. The idea that there must be a copy-text was so firmly rooted in his mind that the only alternative he saw to selecting a single radiating text was to have a "non-extant copy-text" (p. 471), in Crane's case the lost syndicate master proofs as reconstructed from the radiating texts. To cling to a concept of "copy-text" even if it comes to mean the same thing as the scholar's reconstructed text is surely the ultimate in being tyrannized by the idea of having something called "copy-text." At the end of the essay Bowers says that to try applying Greg's rationale to radiating-text situations "would establish a real tyranny of the copy-text"; but Bowers (like Greg before him) was not able, even while warning others about this tyranny, to shake himself entirely free from its bonds.
IV
Two years after Bowers's essay, I called attention to the inappropriateness of trying to employ in radiating-text situations the kind of apparatus that had become standard, under Bowers's influence, for use with linear genealogies. Although he recognized that Greg's "Rationale" did not apply to radiating texts, he apparently could not bring himself to accept fully the fact that an apparatus reflecting this rationale would not do so, either. It is noteworthy that when, in "Multiple Authority," he shrank from the notion of a "non-extant copy-text" his stated reason was not conceptual but the belief that "the problem of what form an apparatus
There is no escaping the fact that radiating texts equidistant from their common ancestor provide no text to serve as copy-text; and it is further true that this lack does not prevent an editor from constructing
The difference between the two may at first seem slight, a matter of labeling: in the former, one lets a copy-text reading stand if the variant is indifferent and there is thus no compelling argument for altering it; in the latter, two readings that might otherwise be indifferent are not actually so, for the fact that one of them comes from a text of superior genealogical standing provides a reason for choosing it. But the difference between these two justifications for the same decision is not superficial: it goes to the heart of what critical editing is. The key point is not whether an editor would make the same decision by following Greg's rationale or by designating no copy-text but still following Greg's argument for the presumptive authority of the text closest to an authorial manuscript. No two editors can be expected to make the same choices by following either of these systems in any case. The important point is that the former approach places a rule above reason (as any recourse to a fall-back position must do), whereas the latter restructures the problem so that the editor's decision (even if it is the same decision) results from the positive step of taking a reasoned action.
The controlling images of the two approaches are those of initially
The constructive approach I am outlining subsumes all the various points of view that can be taken toward the goal of editing. There is no reason, for example, why an editor interested in uninfluenced authorial final intention could not still follow Greg's rationale—which has proved itself effective for this purpose. But instead of treating one text as a copy-text, an editor would use the genealogical position—and thus the presumed authority—of that text as a factor in weighing each variant reading. Sometimes this factor would be decisive; sometimes other factors would be. The difference between this procedure and the conventional one is subtle but crucially significant. Genealogy is taken into account, but with judgment clearly in the dominant position. If, instead of uninfluenced authorial intention, one preferred to emphasize, say, the text that was the joint product of the author and the publisher's staff, one would then have a different attitude toward some of the first-edition readings that vary from manuscript readings (those, for instance, that seem to reflect house-styling). Or if one wished to focus on a stage that preceded a final version, the bulk of the text might be drawn from the document that provides the best evidence of the existence of such a stage,
Despite the salutary emphasis of Greg and Bowers on editorial freedom, many editors are still—as Greg and Bowers were—in thrall to the notion, now about two centuries old, that responsibility in scholarly editing is, at least to some degree, incompatible with freedom of judgment. A passage in Bowers's "Multiple Authority" illustrates how inhibiting this attitude can sometimes be. Bowers claims that the evidence of the radiating newspaper texts of a Crane story enables one to attempt reconstructing the syndicate master proofs but offers no justification for pushing on back to Crane's manuscript. It is not the editor's concern, he says, "whether in their recovered form these proofs agree or disagree with Crane's habits of punctuation, spelling, and so on"; and he continues, more emphatically, to say that "it is not an editor's business to print what he may be morally certain the manuscript reading would have been when the evidence indicates strongly that the recovered proof read otherwise" (p. 473).[30] There may be good reason, of course, to be satisfied with having the text of the syndicate proofs; but if one is really interested in what Crane wrote in his manuscript, and if one's knowledge and judgment make one "morally certain" of being able to reconstruct it, why should one be prevented from doing so by the fact that one is going back two or more steps behind the preserved documents rather than just a single step? The "law" of "documentary evidence," to which Bowers appeals, is surely misapplied if it outlaws the responsible use of the historical imagination. The very existence of critical editing depends on recognizing that documentary texts may legitimately be overruled by
On many other occasions, however, Bowers not only granted, but openly welcomed, the dominance of judgment—as when, in his edition of Tom Jones (1975), after saying that the textual situation was one in which "Greg's classic theory of copy-text must hold" (p. lxx), he declared that the operation of emendation "is a critical process almost exclusively" and that in such a process "the editor shoulders his proper responsibility" (p. lxxi). In a 1985 address he described Greg's rationale as "a discretionary principle, to be applied flexibly," and as a "liberation" from "mechanical conservatism," complaining that in America it was often used to justify "avoiding the unknown terrors of eclecticism."[31] Both Greg and Bowers unquestionably believed in the liberty of editorial judgment, but in their procedural statements they yoked this belief to a strategy that sprang ultimately from a contrary view, for they obviously carried with them just enough of an inherited distrust of judgment to make them not quite prepared for completing the long historical movement toward the full reinstatement of critical judgment in editing.
What I am proposing here is a way to take that step without abandoning the responsibilities of scholarship. It might be called "constructive critical editing" to distinguish it from an approach that emphasizes emendation. To see critical editing as an activity of rebuilding rather than repairing forces the judgment to play its central role in recovering the past. All historical reconstruction requires judgment to enable one to decide what can be accepted as facts and what can reasonably be inferred from them by an informed imagination. Experiencing verbal works as communications from the past entails this kind of reconstruction not only because they are past events but also because they employ an intangible medium, language. Reading necessarily involves the use of judgment in the extracting of a work from a document. If editors' readings, enshrined in editions, are to be exemplary, they must arise from an active embracing of judgment—which is, after all, the only thing we have to rely on.
Notes
This paper was presented as a Book Arts Press lecture during Rare Book School at the University of Virginia, 12 July 1993.
The developments summarized here are sketched more fully (with references to other accounts) in my "Classical, Biblical, and Medieval Textual Criticism and Modern Editing," Studies in Bibliography, 36 (1983), 21-68; reprinted in Textual Criticism and Scholarly Editing (1990), pp. 274-321.
The term "emendation" has come to be used by editors of post-medieval literature to mean any alteration made in a copy-text by a critical editor—that is, alterations that derive from variants in other documentary texts and also alterations that originate with the editor. In the textual criticism of ancient writings, however, the term has traditionally been used to refer only to the editor's own innovations, introduced into a "recension" that resulted from an analysis of the variants in the documentary texts. This older tradition misleadingly encourages a belief that the process of recension is more objective than that of emendation (especially since the usual phrase is "conjectural emendation"), whereas the newer usage, which carries no such implication, is more realistic. This point is discussed more fully on pp. 25-27 [278-280] of the essay cited in the preceding note.
A "diplomatic" text is one that aims to reproduce without alteration the textual features of a document (primarily the words and punctuation), but not those features that can, in the particular instance, be regarded as nontextual (such as the letterforms or the page layout). See also note 7 below.
I have attempted to survey recent thinking along these lines in "Textual Criticism and Literary Sociology," SB, 44 (1991), 83-143.
The difficulty of segregating the intentions of specific individuals will vary from one instance to another; but even when the difficulty seems extreme, there is no reason not to apply informed judgment to the attempt, if one is sufficiently interested.
Some works, of course, entail the combining (or "mixing") of media: thus there are instances in which works are partially verbal and partially visual, such as shaped or concrete poetry. The dividing line between what is textual and what is nontextual in the physical features of a document must be determined separately in each instance. Features judged to be nontextual (not part of the work) are not necessarily irrelevant as evidence for reconstructing the work; indeed, all physical characteristics of a document must be scrutinized carefully by the editor, since none can be automatically ruled out as unrelated to textual considerations. Cf. note 28 below.
The fear of "eclecticism"—expressed often in the history of scholarly editing—is generally based on a failure to understand that versions (like works) cannot be found in the texts of specific documents. The most extended discussion of eclecticism in editing is Fredson Bowers's "Remarks on Eclectic Texts," Proof, 4 (1975), 31-76; reprinted in his Essays in Bibliography, Text, and Editing (1975), pp. 488-528.
For a fuller statement of the ideas outlined here, see my A Rationale of Textual Criticism (1989). It is surprising that some textual critics label this view of literary works "Platonic." Recognition of the intangible nature of certain media is independent of a general belief in the secondary status of the physical world. A Platonist would of course take a Platonic view of both intangible and tangible media; but the concept of intangibility is not in itself Platonic.
This preface is conveniently excerpted in Housman's Selected Prose, ed. John Carter (1961), pp. 23-44 (quotation from p. 43) and in Collected Poems and Selected Prose, ed. Christopher Ricks (1988), pp. 372-386 (quotation not included.)
McKerrow's sentence ends with an unexceptionable statement of one editorial goal: "to present those [the author's] works as he believes the author to have intended them to appear." But McKerrow's point is only to distinguish between the editor's own preferences and the editor's conclusions as to what the author's preferences were; he does not acknowledge the role that editorial judgment, especially as applied to every variant individually, might play in moving toward his chosen goal.
For Fredson Bowers's fuller analysis of McKerrow's illogical caution, see "McKerrow's Editorial Principles for Shakespeare Reconsidered," Shakespeare Quarterly, 6 (1955), 309-324. Bowers also explored some of Greg's differences from McKerrow in "McKerrow, Greg, and 'Substantive Edition,'" Library, 5th ser., 33 (1978), 83-107.
Greg's essay was first published in SB, 3 (1950-51), 19-36, and was reprinted in Greg's Collected Papers, ed. J. C. Maxwell (1966), pp. 374-391 (the latter text is cited here). The evolution of Greg's thought preceding this essay can be observed in his "McKerrow's Prolegomena Reconsidered," Review of English Studies, 17 (1941), 139-149, and in the prefaces to the first two printings of his The Editorial Problem in Shakespeare (1942, 1951).
In the original publication of the "Rationale," Greg did not indicate that in saying "what may be called the tyranny of the copy-text" he was not inventing the phrase himself; but in an added footnote, included in the 1966 republication of the essay, he attributed it to Paul Maas, who had used it in a review (Review of English Studies, 20 [1944], 76) of Greg's The Editorial Problem in Shakespeare when he was commenting on Greg's interest in preserving copy-text spelling.
In the course of one of the more incisive analyses of Greg's position, T. H. Howard-Hill distinguishes two senses of "indifferent," one referring to the inability of an editor to judge between two readings and the other referring to the equal authority of the sources from which two readings come. In the practice of editing, however, these meanings must merge, since one's judgment of a reading takes the source of the reading into account, and one's evaluation of a source involves an analysis of its readings. See his "Modern Textual Theories and the Editing of Plays," Library, 6th ser., 11 (1989), 89-115; and my discussion of it in "Textual Criticism and Literary Sociology" (note 4 above), pp. 122-128 (esp. p. 123 and footnote 60). Tom Davis, in an earlier cogent discussion of Greg's rationale, also examines the crucial matter of what it means to label a variant "indifferent," suggesting that this action reinforces "the tyranny of the copy-text"; see "The CEAA and Modern Textual Editing," Library, 5th ser., 32 (1977), 61-74 (esp. pp. 69-71), and my comments on it in "Recent Editorial Discussion and the Central Questions of Editing," SB, 34 (1981), 23-65 (esp. pp. 40-42), reprinted in Textual Criticism since Greg (1987), pp. 65-107 (esp. pp. 82-84).
For an evaluative survey of the commentary, see my Textual Criticism since Greg (1987), supplemented by the essay cited in note 4 above.
The first, a paper read before the Bibliographical Society in London, was published in the Library, 5th ser., 27 (1972), 81-115, and was reprinted in his Essays in Bibliography, Text, and Editing (1975), pp. 447-487 (the text cited here). The second paper was published in SB, 31 (1978), 90-161.
At one point (p. 459) Bowers says that before Greg the conservative position regarding the accidentals of a revised edition (essentially McKerrow's belief that they must be accepted) was "partly based on despair." Yet Greg's different recommendation—to follow the accidentals of the unrevised edition—was equally uncritical and equally a counsel of despair, founded in part—as Greg said—on "philological ignorance" (p. 377). Both positions illustrate the tendency to turn away from evaluative judgment in cases of "ignorance."
The kind of apparatus Bowers had in mind, as he made clear in his footnote 20, was one in which a list of emendations records all editorial alterations to the copy-text (accidentals as well as substantives) and a "historical collation" records only the substantive variants in the collated documents. In this system, the choice of copy-text does not affect the length of the tabulation of substantive variants (since all are recorded in one list or another), but it does change the length of the listing of accidentals unless the number of required emendations of copy-text accidentals happens to be the same in any case. Bowers recognizes, at least in the instance of a revised-edition copy-text, that the unlisted first-edition variants in accidentals are of legitimate interest to the reader; and the only explanation he offers for not noting them is that it is "usually impracticable to record in the Historical Collation all rejected accidentals as well as substantives."
He reports that in his edition of Tom Jones "proportionately far more indifferent variants are inserted from the revised edition into the first-edition copy-text than in the conservatively treated Joseph Andrews" (p. 159).
The year before, however, in Tales of Whilomville (1969), he postulated that the McClure's and Cornhill texts of "His New Mittens" radiated from Crane's manuscript. But the evidence here is not conclusive, as it is with the syndicated newspaper pieces.
See, for example, the discussion of "A Mystery of Heroism": the six newspaper texts "are technically of equal authority," but "For convenience the Philadelphia Press printing has been selected as copy-text, since it is representative. It is reprinted here, emended as necessary by reference to the other authorities when it appears to wander whether in accidentals or in substantives from the majority view" (p. lxix). In the case of "The Clan of No-Name," the conjectural textual history "places each of the preserved documents as technically equal in authority with the others in respect to the accidentals" (p. cxix); but the "usual moderate position" of the New York Herald "in respect to what may be reconstructed as the accidentals of the lost typescript makes it the most satisfactory and convenient copy-text" (p. cxxiii).
But not always: sometimes, he asserts, "only general concurrence of the following editions is in question and exactness of detail would serve no useful purpose." In those cases he introduces a plus/minus sign to signify that the majority of the newspaper texts (but not all of them) have the cited punctuation. He adds, "If it seemed important to indicate that certain of these variant texts had such and such punctuation, then the listing would do so as most convenient." (See 6: 335-336.)
In making this point (p. 466), he overstates the mechanical nature of the establishment of accidentals under Greg's rationale; as Bowers elsewhere recognizes (and as Greg himself does in the "Rationale"), copy-text accidentals, like the substantives, can be emended whenever one has a basis (necessarily involving critical judgment) for doing so.
In a footnote Bowers acknowledges, "Paradoxically, the copy-text most faithful to the reconstructed printer's-copy conceals more information in its list of emendations by recording fewer of the multiple variants than would be the case for a copy-text less faithful." His response to this problem is not satisfactory, however, because it concentrates on a "limited" recording of additional variants and does not admit the logical necessity of a full report: "How far this concealment of the evidence on which the work was edited can be rectified by including among the substantive variants of the Historical Collation the accidentals variants rejected from the other witnesses is a procedure sometimes practicable on a limited basis." An editor who pursues this idea can, Bowers believes, "start by omitting at least the unique variants—since these will have little or no claim to authority—and then progress up the scale so far as seems practicable." But this thinking is at odds with the important point made earlier that a critical approach to variants must take precedence over a merely statistical one. (In a later volume of the edition [volume 3 but published in 1976], The Third Violet and Active Service, Bowers specifically notes that "a minority, or even a single newspaper, may on some very few occasions reflect more faithfully the proof than the styled majority" [p. 332].)
See "Editorial Apparatus for Radiating Texts," Library, 5th ser., 29 (1974), 330-337; reprinted in Textual Criticism and Scholarly Editing (1990), pp. 167-176 (and see my comment on p. xiii of the preface to this volume, suggesting that "the idea of editing without a copy-text, set forth briefly here in relation to one particular kind of situation, has further applications that ought to be explored"). Bowers commented on my 1974 article the following year in his "Remarks on Eclectic Texts" (see note 8 above); after saying that a copy-text selected from a group of radiating texts is "only a peg on which to hang the apparatus of variation," he refers to my "interesting proposal," which—though it seems "logically planned"—he has not "had the opportunity to test" (p. 507, footnote 26). In his 1978 essay on Greg, he repeats the idea that for radiating texts the "choice of copy-text rests on the convenience of the reader according to the ease with which he can refer to the apparatus"; then he adds, "On the other hand, if an editor chooses to adopt G. T. Tanselle's ingenious suggestions for a new kind of apparatus for radiating texts, the need for an arbitrary copy-text vanishes" (p. 149, footnote 48). (In the same footnote, Bowers suggests, without realizing it, a way in which the editorial thinking involved in a radiating-text situation could be extended to any instance of variant texts: when a statistical survey of variants determines the choice of a radiating copy-text, he says, "there should be little if any need for an editor to rely on any accidental in the copy-text simply because it occurs in the copy-text, although he may of course take that fact into account when the copy-text document seems on the whole to be relatively faithful and all other evidence is indifferent.") For a similar discussion of apparatus for radiating texts nine years later, see p. 76 of Bowers's "Mixed Texts and Multiple Authority," Text, 3 (1987), 63-90.
In "Mixed Texts and Multiple Authority" (see the preceding note), he includes in a footnote the explicit statement, "It is quite improper to use it [copy-text] as a synonym for printer's copy in general" (p. 87). For a more detailed account of this distinction, see my "The Meaning of Copy-Text: A Further Note," SB, 23 (1970), 191-196. When I submitted this piece—which is a rejoinder to Paul Baender's "The Meaning of Copy-Text" in the previous volume of SB (22 [1969], 311-318)—Bowers said that he had planned (before my piece came in) to write such a response himself.
Leonard E. Boyle calls modern editors "scribe-scholars" in "'Epistulae Venerunt Parum Dulces': The Place of Codicology in the Editing of Medieval Latin Texts," in Editing and Editors: A Retrospect, ed. Richard Landon (1988), pp. 29-46 (see p. 30). (This essay also provides a useful statement of the value of examining the physical "setting" in which a text has been transmitted; the examples are drawn from the study of early manuscripts, but the points made are equally applicable to the study of printed books—and have of course been made many times by analytical bibliographers.)
The inhibiting influence of a copy-text resembles the pressure that can also be exerted by a previous scholarly edition: Leonard Boyle has said, "the greatest threat to an editor's independence and to an unprejudiced presentation of a textual tradition is the presence of an existing edition." See "'Epistulae Venerunt Parum Dulces'" (cited in the preceding note), p. 31.
| ||