Section 86. (2) The View, of the Uneducated.
"To discourse is nature, to assimilate discourse as it is given, is
culture." With this statement, Goethe has shown where the deficiencies
in culture begin, and observation verifies the fact that the
uncultured person is unable to accept what is told him as it is told
him. This does not mean that uncultured people are unable to
remember statements as they are made, but that they are unable
to assimilate any perception in its integrity and to reproduce it
in its natural simplicity. This is the alpha and the omega of every
thing observable in the examination of simple people. Various
thinkers in different fields have noted this fact. Mill, e. g., observes
that the inability to distinguish between perception and inference
is most obvious in the attempt of some ignorant person to describe
a natural phenomenon. Douglas Stewart notices that the village
apothecary will rarely describe the simplest case without immediately
making use of a terminology in which every word is a theory. The
simple and true presentation of the phenomenon will reveal at once
whether the mind is able to give an accurate interpretation of nature.
This suggests why we are frequently engaged in some much-involved
process of description of a fact, in itself simple. It has been presented
to us in this complicated fashion because our informants did not
know how to speak simply. So Kant: "The testimony of common
people may frequently be intended honestly, but it is not often
reliable because the witnesses have not the habit of prolonged attention,
and so they mistake what they think themselves for what they
hear from others. Hence, even though they take oaths, they can
hardly be believed." Hume, again, says somewhere in the Essay,
that most men are naturally inclined to differentiate their discourse,
inasmuch as they see their object from one side only, do not think
of the objections, and conceive its corroborative principles with
such liveliness that they pay no attention to those which look another
way. Now, whoever sees an object from one side only does not see
it as it comes to him, and whoever refuses to think of objections, has
already subjectively colored his objects and no longer sees them
as they are.
In this regard it is interesting to note the tendency of uneducated
people to define things. They are not interested in the immediate
perception, but in its abstract form. The best example of this is
the famous barrack-room definition of honor: Honor is that thing
belonging to the man who has it. The same fault is committed by
anybody who fails to apprehend the
whole as it
comes, but perceives
only what is most obvious and nearest. Mittermaier has pointed
out that the light-minded, accidental witness sees only the nearest
characteristics. Again, he says, "It is a well-known fact that
uneducated people attend only to the question that was asked them
last."
[1] This fact is
important. If a witness is unskilfully asked in
one breath whether he murdered A, robbed B, and stole a pear
from C, he will probably answer with calmness, "No, I have not
stolen a pear," but he pays no attention to the other two portions
of the question. This characteristic is frequently made use of by
the defense. The lawyers ask some important witness for the prosecution:
"Can you say that you have seen how the accused entered
the room, looked around, approached the closet, and then drew the
watch toward himself?" The uneducated witness then says dryly,
"No, I can not say that," although he has seen everything except
the concealment of the watch. He denies the whole thing solely
because he has been able to attend to the last portion of the question
only. It is very easy to look out for these characteristics, by simply
not permitting a number of questions in one, by having questions
put in the simplest and clearest possible form. Simple questions
are thankfully received, and get better answers than long, or tricky
ones.
For the same reason that prevents uneducated people from ever
seeing a thing as it comes to them, their love of justice depends
on their eagerness to avoid becoming themselves subjects of injustice.
Hence, weak people can never be honest, and most uneducated
people understand by duty that which others are to
do.
Duty is presented as required of all men, but it is more comfortable
to require it of others, so that it is understood as only so required.
It may be due to the fact that education develops quiet imperturbability,
and that this is conducive to correcter vision and more
adequate objectivity in both events and obligations.
There is another series of processes which are characteristic of
the point of view of the uneducated. There is, e. g., a peculiar
recurring mental process with regard to the careful use of life
preservers, fire extinguishers, and other means of escape, which are to
be used hastily in case of need. They are found
always carefully
chained up, or hidden in closets by the ignorant. This is possible
only if the idea of protecting oneself against sudden need does not
make itself effective as such, but is forced out of the mind by the
desire to protect oneself against theft.
Why must the uneducated carefully feel everything that is shown
them, or that they otherwise find to be new? Children even smell
such things, while educated people are satisfied with looking at
them. The request in public places, "Do not touch," has very
good reason. I believe that the level of culture of an individual
may be determined without much mistake, by his inclination to
touch or not to touch some new object presented him. The reason
for this desire can hardly be established but it is certainly the wish
of the uneducated to study the object more fundamentally and
hence, to bring into play other senses than that of sight. It may
be that the educated man sees more because he is better trained in
careful observation, so that the uneducated man is really compelled
to do more than merely to look. On the other hand, it may be that
the uneducated man here again fails to perceive the object as it
is, and when it appears to him as object A, or is indicated as that
object, he is inclined to disbelieve, and must convince himself by
careful feeling that it is really
an A.[2]
It may be, again, that "trains
of association" can help to explain the matter.
That an understanding of the character of an object is dependent
on training and educated observation has been verified many times,
incidentally, also by the fact that the uneducated find it difficult
to get on with representations. Now this can not be accounted for
by only their defective practice. The old, but instructive story of
the peasant-woman who asked her son what he was reading, the
black or the white, repeats itself whenever uneducated people are
shown images, photographs, etc. For a long time I had not noticed
that they see the background as the thing to be attended to. When,
for example, you show an uneducated man a bust photograph, it
may happen that he perceives the upper surroundings of shoulder
and head as the lower contours of the background which is to indicate
some fact, and if these contours happen to be, e. g., those of a dog,
the man sees "a white dog." This is more frequent than we think,
and hence, we must pay little attention to failures to recognize
people in photographs.[3] One more
story by way of example—
that of a photographer who snapped a dozen parading young dragoons,
and had gotten the addresses, but not the street numbers of
their parents. He sent for that reason to the twelve parents, for
inspection, a photograph each with the notice that if some mistake
had occurred he would rectify it. But not a parent complained of
the photographer's failure to have sent them the pictures of their
own children. Each had received a soldier, and appeared to be quite
satisfied with the correctness of his image. Hence it follows again,
that denials of photographic identity by the uneducated are altogether
without value.
In another direction images have a peculiar significance for children
and ignorant people, because they show ineradicable ideas, particularly
with regard to size. Nobody recalls any book so vividly
as his first picture book and its contents. We remember it even
though we are convinced that the people who made our picture
book were quite mistaken. Now, as it frequently happens that the
sizes are incorrectly reproduced, as when, e. g., a horse and a reindeer
occur in the same picture, and the latter seems bigger than the former,
the reindeer appears in imagination always bigger. It does not
matter if we learn later how big a reindeer is, or how many times we
have seen one, we still find the animal "altogether too small, it
must be bigger than a horse." Educated adults do not make this
mistake, but the uneducated do, and many false statements depend
on ideas derived from pictures. If their derivation is known we may
discover the source of the mistake, but if the mistake occurred
unconsciously, then we have to combine the circumstances and study
further to find the reason.
Finally, the general influence of the failure of ignorant people to
see things as they are, upon their feeling-tone is shown in two
characteristic stories. Bulwer tells of a servant whose master beat him
and who was instigated to seek protection in court. He refused
indignantly inasmuch as his master was too noble a person to be
subject to law. And Gutberlet tells the story of the director of police,
Serafini, in Ravenna, who had heard that a notorious murderer had
threatened to shoot him. Serafini had the assassin brought to him,
gave him a loaded pistol and invited him to shoot. The murderer
grew pale and Serafini boxed his ears and kicked him out.
[[ id="n86.1"]]
Die Lehre vom Beweise. Darmstadt 1843.
[[ id="n86.2"]]
Cf H. Gross's Archiv, II, 140, III, 350; VII, 155.
[[ id="n86.3"]]
Cf H. Gross's Archiv, VII, 160.