University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
  
expand section 
  
expand section 
  

expand section1. 
expand section2. 
expand section3. 
expand section4. 
expand section5. 
expand section6. 
expand section7. 
expand section8. 
expand section9. 
expand section10. 
expand section11. 
expand section12. 
expand section13. 
expand section14. 
expand section15. 
expand section16. 
expand section17. 
expand section18. 
expand section19. 
expand section20. 
expand section21. 
expand section22. 
expand section23. 
expand section24. 
expand section25. 
expand section26. 
expand section27. 
expand section28. 
collapse section29. 
collapse section29.1. 
1. Of the Spirit of a Legislator.
  
  
expand section29.2. 
 29.3. 
 29.4. 
expand section29.5. 
expand section29.6. 
expand section29.7. 
expand section29.8. 
expand section29.10. 
expand section29.10. 
expand section29.11. 
expand section29.12. 
expand section29.13. 
expand section29.14. 
expand section29.15. 
expand section29.16. 
expand section29.17. 
 29.18. 
expand section29.19. 
expand section30. 
expand section31. 

29.1. 1. Of the Spirit of a Legislator.

I say it, and methinks I have undertaken this work with no other view than to prove it, the spirit of a legislator ought to be that of moderation; political, like moral good, lying always between two extremes. [1] Let us produce an example.

The set forms of justice are necessary to liberty, but the number of them might be so great as to be contrary to the end of the very laws that established them; processes would have no end; property would be uncertain; the goods of one of the parties would be adjudged to the other without examining, or they would both be ruined by examining too much.

The citizens would lose their liberty and security, the accusers would no longer have any means to convict, nor the accused to justify themselves.

Footnotes

[1]

Aristotle, "Politics," lib. i, chap. 11.