University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
Dictionary of the History of Ideas

Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas
  
  

collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionIV. 
  
collapse sectionIV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionIV. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVII. 
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVII. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse sectionVII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionIII. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
collapse sectionVII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionVI. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionI. 
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionIV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
  
  
  
  
  
collapse sectionII. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionV. 
  
collapse sectionIV. 
  

1. All founders of the utility theory had some doubts
about the cardinal measurability of utility, but they
took for granted that the utility of each commodity
is independent of other commodities, that the utility
of bacon, for instance, does not depend on how many
eggs one has. This means that, if x1, x2,..., xn denote
the amounts of the various commodities possessed by
an individual, his total utility is the sum of the single
utilities, U1(x1) + U2(x2) + ... + Un(xn). It goes
without saying that the assumption greatly simplifies
the analysis of value. Let John have six bushels of
potatoes which he can trade at the price of four eggs
for a bushel. In Figure 1, let the number of bushels
be measured from O1 to X1 and the number of eggs
from O2 to X2. Let A1C1 represent John's direct mar-
ginal utility of potatoes when consumed as such and
let A2C2 represent his indirect marginal utility of pota-
toes derived from the eggs obtained by trading. If John
wants to maximize his total utility—a basic assumption
of every utility theory—he should, obviously, trade the
sixth and fifth bushels: their indirect utility is greater
than their direct utility. And he should stop trading
at the point M, where the two curves intersect, because
the direct utility of the fourth bushel is greater for him
than its indirect utility. And if John possessed initially
twenty-four eggs instead of six bushels of potatoes, he
should end up with the same distribution of commodi-
ties, four bushels of potatoes and eight eggs. The same
result obtains in the equivalent case in which John has
twelve dollars and the prices are two dollars for a
bushel and fifty cents for an egg. But if, as it may well
happen, the marginal utilities are such that A1C1 and
A2C2 do not meet, then John must choose to have
either only potatoes or only eggs, according to which
commodity has everywhere a greater marginal utility.
In any case, the optimal distribution of the budget is
unique, which is a direct consequence of the Principle
of Decreasing Marginal Utility.

The fact that a glance at Figure 1 suffices to clarify
many issues of value is the reason why economists still
use this highly unrealistic framework. For example, the
diagram (with A1C1 and A2C2 being drawn as they are)
shows that John's dollar buys more utility when spent
on potatoes than on eggs. This simple point explains
away the paradox of value. The same diagram shows
that as a potato seller John gains the amount of utility
represented by the area MA2C1, and as an egg seller
he gains the greater amount MA1C2 (which may be
infinite if the first potato is indispensable to life). There
can be then no just exchange in Aristotle's sense. And
to know whether there are just exchanges in Turgot's
sense we need the interpersonal comparison of utilities
in which Bentham believed.