University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
Dictionary of the History of Ideas

Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas
  
  
expand section 
  
expand section 
  
  

expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
collapse sectionIII. 
  
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 

Law and Religion. Causation is a leading motif in
most religions: the ways in which the world comes into
existence and is sustained, and the modes by which
man may discharge religious obligation. Each notion
involves a theory of causation. A religion's cosmology
issues in its science, primitive or advanced; the obliga-
tions imposed on man by his religion are his first law.
All the ramifications of the idea of causation in religious
history have this dual character. Causation is either
physical or purposive, according as its referent is na-
ture or human conduct. Causation in law retains the
two strands, though its concern is much more with
human action than with the order of physical events.

In the history of Western religion, God is said to
have caused the world to come into existence and to
govern it through his laws (note the legal reference).
In the Bible, the cosmogonic account of the origin of
the universe is scant and primitive; the laws governing
man are detailed and sophisticated, so much so that
the original document comes to be known as the Book
of the Law (Torah, in Hebrew). There was an early
development of a widespread casuistic activity which
has never ceased to occupy the Hebraic religions.
Religious law concerns itself with the limits of human
obligation or responsibility, and inherent in all such
legislation or decision is a notion of causation. It is
usually assumed that a man is responsible for the state
of affairs which he has caused. The extent to which
he may be held responsible for events he has not caused
is a matter of deep and continuing perplexity.

Out of this religious practice grew one major strand
of the idea of causation in law. And since law becomes
separated from religion, if at all, only in the late matu-
rity of religion, it is easy to see how important religious
beliefs in the matter of causation are to legal develop-
ment. In brief, religion bequeaths to law the notion
of moral responsibility for man's interventions in the
regular course of nature and for impositions of his will
upon nature and society. It may or may not hold him
responsible for what he does in a state of divine mad-
ness, atē, karma, or fate. “Not I was the cause of this
act,” said Agamemnon, “but Zeus and the Erinys who
walks in darkness: they it was who in the assembly
put wild atē in my understanding, on that day when
I arbitrarily took Achilles' prize” (Dodds, 1957). A
modern pleader might say, “Not guilty because of
temporary insanity.”