University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
Dictionary of the History of Ideas

Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas
  
  
expand section 
  
expand section 
  
  

expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
collapse sectionVII. 
  
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 

The opinion of many historians and philosophers is
that the concept of beauty, like other universal ideas
(for instance, nature, truth), is a vague and empty
abstraction. Yet, beauty has often been defined. During
many great cultural periods, artists who created works
and critics who established the norms and the theory
of these works stated what beauty is, and it seems
preposterous to assert that those who have felt to be
in the presence of beauty deceived themselves. Un-
doubtedly the person who has this feeling or inner
certitude not only means something which is very
relevant to him, but also something which he believes
to be inherent in the object thus characterized. On the
other hand, it is equally certain that the peculiar qual-
ity called beautiful is not the same at all times and
for all persons; nor can we deny that a variety of
subjective and objective factors influence our opinion
that something is beautiful. A brief survey of the types
of answers that have been formulated on this issue may
illustrate its relevance.

In English the term beauty goes back to the French
beauté, which in turn is derived from a conjectured
vulgar Latin bellitatem, formed after the adjective
bellus, which neither originally nor properly desig-
nated something beautiful; pulcher and formosus had
this function. Bellus was a diminutive of bonus (good)
and was used first for women and children, then ironi-
cally for men. Its affectionate overtones are said to
explain why bellus (and not pulcher) was adopted in
the Romance languages, where it survived either alone
or jointly with formosus. The German schön carries
in its oldest forms the meaning of bright, brilliant, and
also striking, impressive.

It is uncertain whether the adjective or the noun
was used first. Whenever the issue is decided, it will


196

be done not on historical but “philosophical” grounds.
Empiricists and positivists claim priority for the adjec-
tive, metaphysicians for the noun. Homer, who is often
cited in the controversy, uses the adjective kalos. He
applies it to men, women, garments, weapons, cattle,
and dogs and seems to refer to a pleasing, sensuous
characteristic; occasionally he takes kalos in the gen-
eral sense of good, proper, designating a high achieve-
ment or the full realization of a potential. It is doubtful
whether Homer means personified beauty when he uses
the noun kallos.

To be sure, neither the etymology nor the early
history of a term designating a universal idea can
explain the later uses of the term, but it is not without
interest for the student of the long and intricate history
of beauty to see that the ambivalent use of beauty and
goodness, beauty and light or radiance, goes back to
the very origin of the concept, and that already in
Homer's time the term was used comprehensively.

In the following we shall deal with the fundamental
approaches to the question of beauty and with the
factors that enter into the judgment of beauty. No
claim is made to have found a logical classification for
the material, nor for proceeding systematically. We
have tried to be clear and coherent in our necessarily
succinct summaries, and we hope to have established
an intelligible pattern.