14.
CHAPTER XIV
THE NATURE OF SUBJECT MATTER:
1. Subject Matter of Educator and of Learner.
—So far as the nature of subject matter in principle is concerned,
there is nothing to add to what has been said
(See ante, p. 158).
It consists of the facts observed, recalled, read, and talked about, and
the ideas suggested, in course of a development of a situation having a
purpose. This statement needs to be rendered more specific by
connecting it with the materials of school instruction, the studies
which make up the curriculum. What is the significance of our
definition in application to reading, writing, mathematics, history,
nature study, drawing, singing, physics, chemistry, modern and foreign
languages, and so on?
Let us recur to two of the points made earlier in our discussion. The
educator's part in the enterprise of education is to furnish the
environment which stimulates responses and directs the learner's course.
In last analysis, all that the educator can do is modify stimuli so that
response will as surely as is possible result in the formation of
desirable intellectual and emotional dispositions. Obviously studies or
the subject matter of the curriculum have intimately to do with this
business of supplying an environment. The other point is the necessity
of a social environment to give meaning to habits formed. In what we
have termed informal education, subject matter is carried directly in
the matrix of social intercourse. It is what the persons with whom an
individual associates do and say. This fact gives a clew to the
understanding of the subject matter of formal or deliberate instruction.
A connecting link is found in the stories, traditions, songs, and
liturgies which accompany the doings and rites of a primitive social
group. They represent the stock of meanings which have been
precipitated out of previous experience, which are so prized by the
group as to be identified with their conception of their own collective
life. Not being obviously a part of the skill exhibited in the daily
occupations of eating, hunting, making war and peace, constructing rugs,
pottery, and baskets, etc., they are consciously impressed upon the
young; often, as in the initiation ceremonies, with intense emotional
fervor. Even more pains are consciously taken to perpetuate the myths,
legends, and sacred verbal formulae of the group than to transmit the
directly useful customs of the group just because they cannot be picked
up, as the latter can be in the ordinary processes of association.
As the social group grows more complex, involving a greater number of
acquired skills which are dependent, either in fact or in the belief of
the group, upon standard ideas deposited from past experience, the
content of social life gets more definitely formulated for purposes of
instruction. As we have previously noted, probably the chief motive for
consciously dwelling upon the group life, extracting the meanings which
are regarded as most important and systematizing them in a coherent
arrangement, is just the need of instructing the young so as to
perpetuate group life. Once started on this road of selection,
formulation, and organization, no definite limit exists. The invention
of writing and of printing gives the operation an immense impetus.
Finally, the bonds which connect the subject matter of school study with
the habits and ideals of the social group are disguised and covered up.
The ties are so loosened that it often appears as if there were none; as
if subject matter existed simply as knowledge on its own independent
behoof, and as if study were the mere act of mastering it for its own
sake, irrespective of any social values. Since it is highly important
for practical reasons to counter-act this tendency
(See ante, p. 10)
the chief purposes of our theoretical discussion are to make clear the
connection which is so readily lost from sight, and to show in some
detail the social content and function of the chief constituents of the
course of study.
The points need to be considered from the standpoint of instructor and
of student. To the former, the significance of a knowledge of subject
matter, going far beyond the present knowledge of pupils, is to supply
definite standards and to reveal to him the possibilities of the crude
activities of the immature. (i) The material of school studies
translates into concrete and detailed terms the meanings of current
social life which it is desirable to transmit. It puts clearly before
the instructor the essential ingredients of the culture to be
perpetuated, in such an organized form as to protect him from the
haphazard efforts he would be likely to indulge in if the meanings had
not been standardized. (ii) A knowledge of the ideas which have been
achieved in the past as the outcome of activity places the educator in a
position to perceive the meaning of the seeming impulsive and aimless
reactions of the young, and to provide the stimuli needed to direct them
so that they will amount to something. The more the educator knows of
music the more he can perceive the possibilities of the inchoate musical
impulses of a child. Organized subject matter represents the ripe
fruitage of experiences like theirs, experiences involving the same
world, and powers and needs similar to theirs. It does not represent
perfection or infallible wisdom; but it is the best at command to
further new experiences which may, in some respects at least, surpass
the achievements embodied in existing knowledge and works of art.
From the standpoint of the educator, in other words, the various studies
represent working resources, available capital. Their remoteness from
the experience of the young is not, however, seeming; it is real. The
subject matter of the learner is not, therefore, it cannot be, identical
with the formulated, the crystallized, and systematized subject matter
of the adult; the material as found in books and in works of art, etc.
The latter represents the possibilities of the former; not its existing
state. It enters directly into the activities of the expert and the
educator, not into that of the beginner, the learner. Failure to bear
in mind the difference in subject matter from the respective standpoints
of teacher and student is responsible for most of the mistakes made in
the use of texts and other expressions of preëxistent knowledge.
The need for a knowledge of the constitution and functions, in the
concrete, of human nature is great just because the teacher's attitude
to subject matter is so different from that of the pupil. The teacher
presents in actuality what the pupil represents only in
posse. That is,
the teacher already knows the things which the student is only learning.
Hence the problem of the two is radically unlike. When engaged in the
direct act of teaching, the instructor needs to have subject matter at
his fingers' ends; his attention should be upon the attitude and
response of the pupil. To understand the latter in its interplay with
subject matter is his task, while the pupil's mind, naturally, should be
not on itself but on the topic in hand. Or to state the same point in a
somewhat different manner: the teacher should be occupied not with
subject matter in itself but in its interaction with the pupils' present
needs and capacities. Hence simple scholarship is not enough. In fact,
there are certain features of scholarship or mastered subject
matter—taken by itself—which get in the way of effective
teaching unless the instructor's habitual attitude is one of concern
with its interplay in the pupil's own experience. In the first place,
his knowledge extends indefinitely beyond the range of the pupil's
acquaintance. It involves principles which are beyond the immature
pupil's understanding and interest. In and of itself, it may no more
represent the living world of the pupil's experience than the
astronomer's knowledge of Mars represents a baby's acquaintance with the
room in which he stays. In the second place, the method of organization
of the material of achieved scholarship differs from that of the
beginner. It is not true that the experience of the young is
unorganized—that it consists of isolated scraps. But it is
organized in connection with direct practical centers of interest. The
child's home is, for example, the organizing center of his geographical
knowledge. His own movements about the locality, his journeys abroad,
the tales of his friends, give the ties which hold his items of
information together. But the geography of the geographer, of the one
who has already developed the implications of these smaller experiences,
is organized on the basis of the relationship which the various facts
bear to one another—not the relations which they bear to his
house, bodily movements, and friends. To the one who is learned,
subject matter is extensive, accurately defined, and logically
interrelated. To the one who is learning, it is fluid, partial, and
connected through his personal occupations.
[10]
The problem of teaching is to
keep the experience of the student moving in the direction of what the
expert already knows. Hence the need that the teacher know both subject
matter and the characteristic needs and capacities of the student.
2. The Development of Subject Matter in the Learner.
—It is possible, without doing violence to the facts, to mark off
three fairly typical stages in the growth of subject matter in the
experience of the learner.
In its first estate, knowledge exists as the content of intelligent
ability—power to do. This kind of subject matter, or known material,
is expressed in familiarity or acquaintance with things. Then this
material gradually is surcharged and deepened through communicated
knowledge or information. Finally, it is enlarged and worked over into
rationally or logically organized material—that of the one who,
relatively speaking, is expert in the subject.
I. The knowledge which comes first to persons, and that remains most
deeply ingrained, is knowledge of how to do; how to walk, talk, read,
write, skate, ride a bicycle, manage a machine, calculate, drive a
horse, sell goods, manage people, and so on indefinitely. The popular
tendency to regard instinctive acts which are adapted to an end as a
sort of miraculous knowledge, while unjustifiable, is evidence of the
strong tendency to identify intelligent control of the means of action
with knowledge. When education, under the influence of a scholastic
conception of knowledge which ignores everything but scientifically
formulated facts and truths, fails to recognize that primary or initial
subject matter always exists as matter of an active doing, involving the
use of the body and the handling of material, the subject matter of
instruction is isolated from the needs and purposes of the learner, and
so becomes just a something to be memorized and reproduced upon demand.
Recognition of the natural course of development, on the contrary,
always sets out with situations which involve learning by doing. Arts
and occupations form the initial stage of the curriculum, corresponding
as they do to knowing how to go about the accomplishment of ends.
Popular terms denoting knowledge have always retained the connection
with ability in action lost by academic philosophies. Ken and can are
allied words. Attention means caring for a thing, in the sense of both
affection and of looking out for its welfare. Mind means carrying out
instructions in action—as a child minds his mother—and
taking care of something—as a nurse minds the baby. To be
thoughtful, considerate, means to heed the claims of others.
Apprehension means dread of undesirable consequences, as well as
intellectual grasp. To have good sense or judgment is to know the
conduct a situation calls for; discernment is not making distinctions
for the sake of making them, an exercise reprobated as hair splitting,
but is insight into an affair with reference to acting. Wisdom has
never lost its association with the proper direction of life. Only in
education, never in the life of farmer, sailor, merchant, physician, or
laboratory experimenter, does knowledge mean primarily a store of
information aloof from doing.
Having to do with things in an intelligent way issues in acquaintance or
familiarity. The things we are best acquainted with are the things we
put to frequent use—such things as chairs, tables, pen, paper,
clothes, food, knives and forks on the commonplace level,
differentiating into more special objects according to a person's
occupations in life. Knowledge of things in that intimate and emotional
sense suggested by the word acquaintance is a precipitate from our
employing them with a purpose. We have acted with or upon the thing so
frequently that we can anticipate how it will act and react—such
is the meaning of familiar acquaintance. We are ready for a familiar
thing; it does not catch us napping, or play unexpected tricks with us.
This attitude carries with it a sense of congeniality or friendliness,
of ease and illumination; while the things with which we are not
accustomed to deal are strange, foreign, cold, remote, "abstract."
II. But it is likely that elaborate statements regarding this primary
stage of knowledge will darken understanding. It includes practically
all of our knowledge which is not the result of deliberate technical
study. Modes of purposeful doing include dealings with persons as well
as things. Impulses of communication and habits of intercourse have to
be adapted to maintaining successful connections with others; a large
fund of social knowledge accrues. As a part of this intercommunication
one learns much from others. They tell of their experiences and of the
experiences which, in turn, have been told them. In so far as one is
interested or concerned in these communications, their matter becomes a
part of one's own experience. Active connections with others are such
an intimate and vital part of our own concerns that it is impossible to
draw sharp lines, such as would enable us to say, "Here my experience
ends; there yours begins." In so far as we are partners in common
undertakings, the things which others communicate to us as the
consequences of their particular share in the enterprise blend at once
into the experience resulting from our own special doings. The ear is
as much an organ of experience as the eye or hand; the eye is available
for reading reports of what happens beyond its horizon. Things remote
in space and time affect the issue of our actions quite as much as
things which we can smell and handle. They really concern us, and,
consequently, any account of them which assists us in dealing with
things at hand falls within personal experience.
Information is the name usually given to this kind of subject matter.
The place of communication in personal doing supplies us with a
criterion for estimating the value of informational material in school.
Does it grow naturally out of some question with which the student is
concerned? Does it fit into his more direct acquaintance so as to
increase its efficacy and deepen its meaning? If it meets these two
requirements, it is educative. The amount heard or read is of no
importance—the more the better, provided the student has
a need for it and can apply it in some situation of his own.
But it is not so easy to fulfill these requirements in actual practice
as it is to lay them down in theory. The extension in modern times of
the area of intercommunication; the invention of appliances for securing
acquaintance with remote parts of the heavens and bygone events of
history; the cheapening of devices, like printing, for recording and
distributing information—genuine and alleged—have created an
immense bulk of communicated subject matter. It is much easier to swamp
a pupil with this than to work it into his direct experiences. All too
frequently it forms another strange world which just overlies the world
of personal acquaintance. The sole problem of the student is to learn,
for school purposes, for purposes of recitations and promotions, the
constituent parts of this strange world. Probably the most conspicuous
connotation of the word knowledge for most persons to-day is just the
body of facts and truths ascertained by others; the material found in
the rows and rows of atlases, cyclopedias, histories, biographies, books
of travel, scientific treatises, on the shelves of libraries.
The imposing stupendous bulk of this material has unconsciously
influenced men's notions of the nature of knowledge itself. The
statements, the propositions, in which knowledge, the issue of active
concern with problems, is deposited, are taken to be themselves
knowledge. The record of knowledge, independent of its place as an
outcome of inquiry and a resource in further inquiry, is taken to be
knowledge. The mind of man is taken captive by the spoils of its prior
victories; the spoils, not the weapons and the acts of waging the battle
against the unknown, are used to fix the meaning of knowledge, of fact,
and truth.
If this identification of knowledge with propositions stating
information has fastened itself upon logicians and philosophers, it is
not surprising that the same ideal has almost dominated instruction.
The "course of study" consists largely of information distributed into
various branches of study, each study being subdivided into lessons
presenting in serial cutoff portions of the total store. In the
seventeenth century, the store was still small enough so that men set up
the ideal of a complete encyclopedic mastery of it. It is now so bulky
that the impossibility of any one man's coming into possession of it all
is obvious. But the educational ideal has not been much affected.
Acquisition of a modicum of information in each branch of learning, or
at least in a selected group, remains the principle by which the
curriculum, from elementary school through college, is formed; the
easier portions being assigned to the earlier years, the more difficult
to the later.
The complaints of educators that learning does not enter into character
and affect conduct; the protests against memoriter work, against
cramming, against gradgrind preoccupation with "facts," against devotion
to wire-drawn distinctions and ill-understood rules and principles, all
follow from this state of affairs. Knowledge which is mainly
second-hand, other men's knowledge, tends to become merely verbal. It
is no objection to information that it is clothed in words;
communication necessarily takes place through words. But in the degree
in which what is communicated cannot be organized into the existing
experience of the learner, it becomes mere words: that is, pure
sense-stimuli, lacking in meaning. Then it operates to call out
mechanical reactions, ability to use the vocal organs to repeat
statements, or the hand to write or to do "sums."
To be informed is to be posted; it is to have at command the subject
matter needed for an effective dealing with a problem, and for giving
added significance to the search for solution and to the solution
itself. Informational knowledge is the material which can be fallen
back upon as given, settled, established, assured in a doubtful
situation. It is a kind of bridge for mind in its passage from doubt to
discovery. It has the office of an intellectual middleman. It
condenses and records in available form the net results of the prior
experiences of mankind, as an agency of enhancing the meaning of new
experiences. When one is told that Brutus assassinated Caesar, or that
the length of the year is three hundred sixty-five and one fourth days,
or that the ratio of the diameter of the circle to its circumference is
3.1415 . . . one receives what is indeed knowledge for others,
but for him it is a stimulus to knowing. His acquisition of
knowledge depends upon his response to what is communicated.
3. Science or Rationalized Knowledge.
—Science is a name for knowledge in its most characteristic form.
It represents in its degree, the perfected outcome of
learning,—its consummation. What is known, in a given case, is
what is sure, certain, settled, disposed of; that which we think with
rather than that which we think about. In its honorable sense,
knowledge is distinguished from opinion, guesswork, speculation, and
mere tradition. In knowledge, things are ascertained; they are so
and not dubiously otherwise. But experience makes us aware that there is
difference between intellectual certainty of subject matter and
our certainty. We are made, so to speak, for belief; credulity is
natural. The undisciplined mind is averse to suspense and intellectual
hesitation; it is prone to assertion. It likes things undisturbed,
settled, and treats them as such without due warrant. Familiarity,
common repute, and congeniality to desire are readily made measuring
rods of truth. Ignorance gives way to opinionated and current
error,—a greater foe to learning than ignorance itself. A
Socrates is thus led to declare that consciousness of ignorance is the
beginning of effective love of wisdom, and a Descartes to say that
science is born of doubting.
We have already dwelt upon the fact that subject matter, or data, and
ideas have to have their worth tested experimentally: that in themselves
they are tentative and provisional. Our predilection for premature
acceptance and assertion, our aversion to suspended judgment, are signs
that we tend naturally to cut short the process of testing. We are
satisfied with superficial and immediate shortvisioned applications.
If these work out with moderate satisfactoriness, we are content to
suppose that our assumptions have been confirmed. Even in the case of
failure, we are inclined to put the blame not on the inadequacy and
incorrectness of our data and thoughts, but upon our hard luck and the
hostility of circumstance. We charge the evil consequence not to the
error of our schemes and our incomplete inquiry into conditions (thereby
getting material for revising the former and stimulus for extending the
latter) but to untoward fate. We even plume ourselves upon our firmness
in clinging to our conceptions in spite of the way in which they work
out.
Science represents the safeguard of the race against these natural
propensities and the evils which flow from them. It consists of the
special appliances and methods which the race has slowly worked out in
order to conduct reflection under conditions whereby its procedures and
results are tested. It is artificial (an acquired art), not
spontaneous; learned, not native. To this fact is due the unique, the
invaluable place of science in education, and also the dangers which
threaten its right use. Without initiation into the scientific spirit
one is not in possession of the best tools which humanity has so far
devised for effectively directed reflection. One in that case not
merely conducts inquiry and learning without the use of the best
instruments, but fails to understand the full meaning of knowledge. For
he does not become acquainted with the traits that mark off opinion and
assent from authorized conviction. On the other hand, the fact that
science marks the perfecting of knowing in highly specialized conditions
of technique renders its results, taken by themselves, remote from
ordinary experience—a quality of aloofness that is popularly
designated by the term abstract. When this isolation appears in
instruction, scientific information is even more exposed to the dangers
attendant upon presenting ready-made subject matter than are other forms
of information.
Science has been defined in terms of method of inquiry and testing. At
first sight, this definition may seem opposed to the current conception
that science is organized or systematized knowledge. The opposition,
however, is only seeming, and disappears when the ordinary definition is
completed. Not organization but the kind of organization effected by
adequate methods of tested discovery marks off science. The knowledge
of a farmer is systematized in the degree in which he is competent. It
is organized on the basis of relation of means to ends—practically
organized. Its organization as knowledge (that is, in the eulogistic
sense of adequately tested and confirmed) is incidental to its
organization with reference to securing crops, live-stock, etc. But
scientific subject matter is organized with specific reference to the
successful conduct of the enterprise of discovery, to knowing as a
specialized undertaking.
Reference to the kind of assurance attending science will shed light
upon this statement. It is rational assurance,—logical
warranty. The ideal of scientific organization is, therefore, that
every conception and statement shall be of such a kind as to follow
from others and to lead to others. Conceptions and propositions mutually
imply and support one another. This double relation of 'leading to and
confirming" is what is meant by the terms logical and rational. The
everyday conception of water is more available for ordinary uses of
drinking, washing, irrigation, etc., than the chemist's notion of it.
The latter's description of it as H20 is superior
from the standpoint of place and use in inquiry. It states the nature of
water in a way which connects it with knowledge of other things, indicating
to one who understands it how the knowledge is arrived at and its bearings
upon other portions of knowledge of the structure of things. Strictly
speaking, it does not indicate the objective relations of water any more
than does a statement that water is transparent, fluid, without taste or
odor, satisfying to thirst, etc. It is just as true that water has
these relations as that it is constituted by two molecules of hydrogen
in combination with one of oxygen. But for the particular purpose
of conducting discovery with a view to ascertainment of fact, the latter
relations are fundamental. The more one emphasizes organization as a
mark of science, then, the more he is committed to a recognition of the
primacy of method in the definition of science. For method defines the
kind of organization in virtue of which science is science.
4. Subject Matter as Social.
—Our next chapters will take up various school activities and
studies and discuss them as successive stages in that evolution of
knowledge which we have just been discussing. It remains to say a few
words upon subject matter as social, since our prior remarks have been
mainly concerned with its intellectual aspect. A difference in breadth
and depth exists even in vital knowledge; even in the data and ideas
which are relevant to real problems and which are motivated by purposes.
For there is a difference in the social scope of purposes and the social
importance of problems. With the wide range of possible material to
select from, it is important that education (especially in all its
phases short of the most specialized) should use a criterion of social
worth.
All information and systematized scientific subject matter have been
worked out under the conditions of social life and have been transmitted
by social means. But this does not prove that all is of equal value for
the purposes of forming the disposition and supplying the equipment of
members of present society. The scheme of a curriculum must take
account of the adaptation of studies to the needs of the existing
community life; it must select with the intention of improving the life
we live in common so that the future shall be better than the past.
Moreover, the curriculum must be planned with reference to placing
essentials first, and refinements second. The things which are socially
most fundamental, that is, which have to do with the experiences in
which the widest groups share, are the essentials. The things which
represent the needs of specialized groups and technical pursuits are
secondary. There is truth in the saying that education must first be
human and only after that professional. But those who utter the saying
frequently have in mind in the term human only a highly specialized
class: the class of learned men who preserve the classic traditions of
the past. They forget that material is humanized in the degree in which
it connects with the common interests of men as men.
Democratic society is peculiarly dependent for its maintenance upon the
use in forming a course of study of criteria which are broadly human.
Democracy cannot flourish where the chief influences in selecting
subject matter of instruction are utilitarian ends narrowly conceived
for the masses, and, for the higher education of the few, the traditions
of a specialized cultivated class. The notion that the "essentials" of
elementary education are the three R's mechanically treated, is based
upon ignorance of the essentials needed for realization of democratic
ideals. Unconsciously it assumes that these ideals are unrealizable; it
assumes that in the future, as in the past, getting a livelihood,
"making a living," must signify for most men and women doing things
which are not significant, freely chosen, and ennobling to those who do
them; doing things which serve ends unrecognized by those engaged in
them, carried on under the direction of others for the sake of pecuniary
reward. For preparation of large numbers for a life of this sort, and
only for this purpose, are mechanical efficiency in reading, writing,
spelling and figuring, together with attainment of a certain amount of
muscular dexterity, "essentials." Such conditions also infect the
education called liberal, with illiberality. They imply a somewhat
parasitic cultivation bought at the expense of not having the
enlightenment and discipline which come from concern with the deepest
problems of common humanity. A curriculum which acknowledges the social
responsibilities of education must present situations where problems are
relevant to the problems of living together, and where observation and
information are calculated to develop social insight and interest.
Summary.
—The subject matter of education consists primarily of the
meanings which supply content to existing social life. The continuity
of social life means that many of these meanings are contributed to
present activity by past collective experience. As social life grows
more complex, these factors increase in number and import. There is
need of special selection, formulation, and organization in order that
they may be adequately transmitted to the new generation. But this very
process tends to set up subject matter as something of value just by
itself, apart from its function in promoting the realization of the
meanings implied in the present experience of the immature. Especially
is the educator exposed to the temptation to conceive his task in terms
of the pupil's ability to appropriate and reproduce the subject matter
in set statements, irrespective of its organization into his activities
as a developing social member. The positive principle is maintained
when the young begin with active occupations having a social origin and
use, and proceed to a scientific insight in the materials and laws
involved, through assimilating into their more direct experience the
ideas and facts communicated by others who have had a larger experience.
Footnotes
[[10]]
Since the learned man should also still be a learner,
it will be understood that these contrasts are relative, not absolute.
But in the earlier stages of learning at least they are practically
all-important.