13.
CHAPTER XIII
THE NATURE OF METHOD:
1. The Unity of Subject Matter and Method.
—The trinity of school topics is subject matter, methods, and
administration or government. We have been concerned with the two former
in recent chapters. It remains to disentangle them from the context in
which they have been referred to, and discuss explicitly their nature.
We shall begin with the topic of method, since that lies closest to the
considerations of the last chapter. Before taking it up, it may be well,
however, to call express attention to one implication of our theory; the
connection of subject matter and method with each other. The idea that mind
and the world of things and persons are two separate and independent
realms—a theory which philosophically is known as dualism—carries
with it the conclusion that method and subject matter of instruction are
separate affairs. Subject matter then becomes a ready-made systematized
classification of the facts and principles of the world of nature and
man. Method then has for its province a consideration of the ways in
which this antecedent subject matter may be best presented to and
impressed upon the mind; or, a consideration of the ways in which the
mind may be externally brought to bear upon the matter so as to
facilitate its acquisition and possession. In theory, at least, one
might deduce from a science of the mind as something existing by itself
a complete theory of methods of learning, with no knowledge of the
subjects to which the methods are to be applied. Since many who are
actually most proficient in various branches of subject matter are
wholly innocent of these methods, this state of affairs gives
opportunity for the retort that pedagogy, as an alleged science of
methods of the mind in learning, is futile;—a mere screen for
concealing the necessity a teacher is under of profound and accurate
acquaintance with the subject in hand.
But since thinking is a
directed movement of subject matter to a completing issue, and since
mind is the deliberate and intentional phase of the process, the notion
of any such split is radically false. The fact that the material of a
science is organized is evidence that it has already been subjected to
intelligence; it has been methodized, so to say. Zoology as a
systematic branch of knowledge represents crude, scattered facts of our
ordinary acquaintance with animals after they have been subjected to
careful examination, to deliberate supplementation, and to arrangement
to bring out connections which assist observation, memory, and further
inquiry. Instead of furnishing a starting point for learning, they mark
out a consummation. Method means that arrangement of subject matter
which makes it most effective in use. Never is method something outside
of the material.
How about method from the standpoint of an individual who is dealing
with subject matter? Again, it is not something external. It is simply
an effective treatment of material—efficiency meaning such
treatment as utilizes the material (puts it to a purpose) with a minimum
of waste of time and energy. We can distinguish a way of acting, and
discuss it by itself; but the way exists only as
way-of-dealing-with-material. Method is not antithetical to subject
matter; it is the effective direction of subject matter to desired
results. It is antithetical to random and ill-considered
action,—ill-considered signifying ill-adapted.
The statement that method means directed movement of subject matter
towards ends is formal. An illustration may give it content. Every
artist must have a method, a technique, in doing his work. Piano
playing is not hitting the keys at random. It is an orderly way of
using them, and the order is not something which exists ready-made in
the musician's hands or brain prior to an activity dealing with the
piano. Order is found in the disposition of acts which use the piano
and the hands and brain so as to achieve the result intended. It is the
action of the piano directed to accomplish the purpose of the piano as a
musical instrument. It is the same with "pedagogical" method. The only
difference is that the piano is a mechanism constructed in advance for a
single end; while the material of study is capable of indefinite uses.
But even in this regard the illustration may apply if we consider the
infinite variety of kinds of music which a piano may produce, and the
variations in technique required in the different musical results
secured. Method in any case is but an effective way of employing some
material for some end.
These considerations may be generalized by going back to the conception
of experience. Experience as the perception of the connection between
something tried and something undergone in consequence is a process.
Apart from effort to control the course which the process takes, there
is no distinction of subject matter and method. There is simply an
activity which includes both what an individual does and what the
environment does. A piano player who had perfect mastery of his
instrument would have no occasion to distinguish between his
contribution and that of the piano. In well-formed, smooth-running
functions of any sort,—skating, conversing, hearing music,
enjoying a landscape,—there is no consciousness of separation of
the method of the person and of the subject matter. In whole-hearted
play and work there is the same phenomenon.
When we reflect upon an experience instead of just having it, we
inevitably distinguish between our own attitude and the objects toward
which we sustain the attitude. When a man is eating, he is eating food.
He does not divide his act into eating and food. But if he makes a
scientific investigation of the act, such a discrimination is the first
thing he would effect. He would examine on the one hand the properties
of the nutritive material, and on the other hand the acts of the
organism in appropriating and digesting. Such reflection upon
experience gives rise to a distinction of what we experience (the
experienced) and the experiencing—the how.
When we give names to this distinction we have subject matter and method
as our terms. There is the thing seen, heard, loved, hated, imagined, and
there is the act of seeing, hearing, loving, hating, imagining, etc.
This distinction is so natural and so important for certain purposes,
that we are only too apt to regard it as a separation in existence and
not as a distinction in thought. Then we make a division between a self
and the environment or world. This separation is the root of the
dualism of method and subject matter. That is, we assume that knowing,
feeling, willing, etc., are things which belong to the self or mind in
its isolation, and which then may be brought to bear upon an independent
subject matter. We assume that the things which belong in isolation to
the self or mind have their own laws of operation irrespective of the
modes of active energy of the object. These laws are supposed to
furnish method. It would be no less absurd to suppose that men can eat
without eating something, or that the structure and movements of the
jaws, throat muscles, the digestive activities of stomach, etc., are not
what they are because of the material with which their activity is
engaged. Just as the organs of the organism are a continuous part of
the very world in which food materials exist, so the capacities of
seeing, hearing, loving, imagining are intrinsically connected with the
subject matter of the world. They are more truly ways in which the
environment enters into experience and functions there than they are
independent acts brought to bear upon things. Experience, in short, is
not a combination of mind and world, subject and object, method and
subject matter, but is a single continuous interaction of a great
diversity (literally countless in number) of energies.
For the purpose of controlling the course or direction which the
moving unity of experience takes we draw a mental distinction between the
how and the what. While there is no way of walking or of eating or of
learning over and above the actual walking, eating, and studying, there
are certain elements in the act which give the key to its more effective
control. Special attention to these elements makes them more obvious to
perception (letting other factors recede for the time being from
conspicuous recognition). Getting an idea of how the experience
proceeds indicates to us what factors must be secured or modified in
order that it may go on more successfully. This is only a somewhat
elaborate way of saying that if a man watches carefully the growth of
several plants, some of which do well and some of which amount to little
or nothing, he may be able to detect the special conditions upon which
the prosperous development of a plant depends. These conditions, stated
in an orderly sequence, would constitute the method or way or manner of
its growth. There is no difference between the growth of a plant and
the prosperous development of an experience. It is not easy, in either
case, to seize upon just the factors which make for its best movement.
But study of cases of success and failure and minute and extensive
comparison, helps to seize upon causes. When we have arranged these
causes in order, we have a method of procedure or a technique.
A consideration of some evils in education that flow from the isolation
of method from subject matter will make the point more definite.
(i) In the first place, there is the neglect (of which we have
spoken) of concrete situations of experience. There can be no discovery
of a method without cases to be studied. The method is derived from
observation of what actually happens, with a view to seeing that it
happen better next time. But in instruction and discipline, there is
rarely sufficient opportunity for children and youth to have the direct
normal experiences from which educators might derive an idea of method
or order of best development. Experiences are had under conditions of
such constraint that they throw little or no light upon the normal
course of an experience to its fruition. "Methods" have then to be
authoritatively recommended to teachers, instead of being an expression
of their own intelligent observations. Under such circumstances, they
have a mechanical uniformity, assumed to be alike for all minds. Where
flexible personal experiences are promoted by providing an environment
which calls out directed occupations in work and play, the methods
ascertained will vary with individuals—for it is certain that each
individual has something characteristic in his way of going at things.
(ii) In the second place, the notion of methods isolated from
subject matter is responsible for the false conceptions of discipline
and interest already noted. When the effective way of managing material
is treated as something ready-made apart from material, there are just
three possible ways in which to establish a relationship lacking by
assumption. One is to utilize excitement, shock of pleasure, tickling
the palate. Another is to make the consequences of not attending
painful; we may use the menace of harm to motivate concern with the
alien subject matter. Or a direct appeal may be made to the person to
put forth effort without any reason. We may rely upon immediate strain
of "will." In practice, however, the latter method is effectual only
when instigated by fear of unpleasant results.
(iii) In the third place, the act of learning is made a direct
and conscious end in itself. Under normal conditions, learning is a
product and reward of occupation with subject matter. Children do not
set out, consciously, to learn walking or talking. One sets out to give
his impulses for communication and for fuller intercourse with others a
show. He learns in consequence of his direct activities. The better
methods of teaching a child, say, to read, follow the same road. They
do not fix his attention upon the fact that he has to learn something
and so make his attitude self-conscious and constrained. They engage
his activities, and in the process of engagement he learns: the same is
true of the more successful methods in dealing with number or whatever.
But when the subject matter is not used in carrying forward impulses and
habits to significant results, it is just something to be learned. The
pupil's attitude to it is just that of having to learn it. Conditions
more unfavorable to an alert and concentrated response would be hard to
devise. Frontal attacks are even more wasteful in learning than in war.
This does not mean, however, that students are to be seduced unaware
into preoccupation with lessons. It means that they shall be occupied
with them for real reasons or ends, and not just as something to be
learned. This is accomplished whenever the pupil perceives the place
occupied by the subject matter in the fulfilling of some experience.
(iv) In the fourth place, under the influence of the conception
of the separation of mind and material, method tends to be reduced to a
cut and dried routine, to following mechanically prescribed steps. No
one can tell in how many schoolrooms children reciting in arithmetic or
grammar are compelled to go through, under the alleged sanction of
method, certain preordained verbal formulae. Instead of being
encouraged to attack their topics directly, experimenting with methods
that seem promising and learning to discriminate by the consequences
that accrue, it is assumed that there is one fixed method to be
followed. It is also naively assumed that if the pupils make their
statements and explanations in a certain form of "analysis," their
mental habits will in time conform. Nothing has brought pedagogical
theory into greater disrepute than the belief that it is identified with
handing out to teachers recipes and models to be followed in teaching.
Flexibility and initiative in dealing with problems are characteristic
of any conception to which method is a way of managing material to
develop a conclusion. Mechanical rigid woodenness is an inevitable
corollary of any theory which separates mind from activity motivated by
a purpose.
2. Method as General and as Individual.
—In brief, the method of teaching is the method of an art, of
action intelligently directed by ends. But the practice of a fine art
is far from being a matter of extemporized inspirations. Study of the
operations and results of those in the past who have greatly succeeded
is essential. There is always a tradition, or schools of art, definite
enough to impress beginners, and often to take them captive. Methods of
artists in every branch depend upon thorough acquaintance with materials
and tools; the painter must know canvas, pigments, brushes, and the
technique of manipulation of all his appliances. Attainment of this
knowledge requires persistent and concentrated attention to objective
materials. The artist studies the progress of his own attempts to see
what succeeds and what fails. The assumption that there are no
alternatives between following ready-made rules and trusting to native
gifts, the inspiration of the moment and undirected "hard work," is
contradicted by the procedures of every art.
Such matters as knowledge of the past, of current technique, of
materials, of the ways in which one's own best results are assured,
supply the material for what may be called general method. There exists
a cumulative body of fairly stable methods for reaching results, a body
authorized by past experience and by intellectual analysis, which an
individual ignores at his peril. As was pointed out in the discussion
of habit-forming
(ante, p. 58),
there is always a danger that these methods will become mechanized and
rigid, mastering an agent instead of being powers at command for his own
ends. But it is also true that the innovator who achieves anything enduring,
whose work is more than a passing sensation, utilizes classic methods more
than may appear to himself or to his critics. He devotes them to new uses,
and in so far transforms them.
Education also has its general methods. And if the application of this
remark is more obvious in the case of the teacher than of the pupil, it
is equally real in the case of the latter. Part of his learning, a very
important part, consists in becoming master of the methods which
the experience of others has shown to be more efficient in like cases of
getting knowledge.
[9]
These general methods are in no way opposed to individual initiative and
originality—to personal ways of doing things. On the contrary they are
reënforcements of them. For there is radical difference between even the
most general method and a prescribed rule. The latter is a direct guide
to action; the former operates indirectly through the enlightenment it supplies
as to ends and means. It operates, that is to say, through intelligence, and
not through conformity to orders externally imposed. Ability to use even in
a masterly way an established technique gives no warranty of artistic
work, for the latter also depends upon an animating idea.
If knowledge of methods used by others does not directly tell us what to
do, or furnish ready-made models, how does it operate? What is meant by
calling a method intellectual? Take the case of a physician. No mode of
behavior more imperiously demands knowledge of established modes of
diagnosis and treatment than does his. But after all, cases are like,
not identical. To be used intelligently, existing practices, however
authorized they may be, have to be adapted to the exigencies of
particular cases. Accordingly, recognized procedures indicate to the
physician what inquiries to set on foot for himself, what measures to
try. They are standpoints from which to carry on investigations; they
economize a survey of the features of the particular case by suggesting
the things to be especially looked into. The physician's own personal
attitudes, his own ways (individual methods) of dealing with the
situation in which he is concerned, are not subordinated to the general
principles of procedure, but are facilitated and directed by the latter.
The instance may serve to point out the value to the teacher of a
knowledge of the psychological methods and the empirical devices found
useful in the past. When they get in the way of his own common sense,
when they come between him and the situation in which he has to act,
they are worse than useless. But if he has acquired them as
intellectual aids in sizing up the needs, resources, and difficulties
of the unique experiences in which he engages, they are of constructive
value. In the last resort, just because everything depends upon
his own methods of response, much depends upon how far he can
utilize, in making his own response, the knowledge which has accrued
in the experience of others.
As already intimated, every word of this account is directly applicable
also to the method of the pupil, the way of learning. To suppose that
students, whether in the primary school or in the university, can be
supplied with models of method to be followed in acquiring and
expounding a subject is to fall into a self-deception that has
lamentable consequences.
(See ante, p. 199.)
One must make his own reaction in any case. Indications of the standardized
or general methods used in like cases by others—particularly by those
who are already experts—are of worth or of harm according as they make
his personal reaction more intelligent or as they induce a person to
dispense with exercise of his own judgment.
If what was said earlier (See p. 159)
about
originality of thought seemed overstrained, demanding more of education
than the capacities of average human nature permit, the difficulty is
that we lie under the incubus of a superstition. We have set up the
notion of mind at large, of intellectual method that is the same for
all. Then we regard individuals as differing in the quantity
of mind with which they are charged. Ordinary persons are then expected
to be ordinary. Only the exceptional are allowed to have originality.
The measure of difference between the average student and the genius is
a measure of the absence of originality in the former. But this notion
of mind in general is a fiction. How one person's abilities compare in
quantity with those of another is none of the teacher's business. It is
irrelevant to his work. What is required is that every individual shall
have opportunities to employ his own powers in activities that have
meaning. Mind, individual method, originality (these are convertible
terms) signify the quality of purposive or directed action. If we
act upon this conviction, we shall secure more originality even by the
conventional standard than now develops. Imposing an alleged uniform
general method upon everybody breeds mediocrity in all but the very
exceptional. And measuring originality by deviation from the mass
breeds eccentricity in them. Thus we stifle the distinctive quality of
the many, and save in rare instances (like, say, that of Darwin) infect
the rare geniuses with an unwholesome quality.
3. The Traits of Individual Method.
—The most general features of the method of knowing have been
given in our chapter on thinking. They are the features of the
reflective situation: Problem, collection and analysis of data,
projection and elaboration of suggestions or ideas, experimental
application and testing; the resulting conclusion or judgment. The
specific elements of an individual's method or way of attack upon a
problem are found ultimately in his native tendencies and his acquired
habits and interests. The method of one will vary from that of another
(and properly vary) as his original instinctive capacities vary,
as his past experiences and his preferences vary. Those who have already
studied these matters are in possession of information which will help
teachers in understanding the responses different pupils make, and help
them in guiding these responses to greater efficiency. Child-study,
psychology, and a knowledge of social environment supplement the
personal acquaintance gained by the teacher. But methods remain the
personal concern, approach, and attack of an individual, and no
catalogue can ever exhaust their diversity of form and tint.
Some attitudes may be named, however,-which are central in effective
intellectual ways of dealing with subject matter. Among the most
important are directness, open-mindedness, single-mindedness (or
whole-heartedness), and responsibility.
1.
It is easier to indicate what is meant by directness through negative
terms than in positive ones. Self-consciousness, embarrassment, and
constraint are its menacing foes. They indicate that a person is not
immediately concerned with subject matter. Something has come between
which deflects concern to side issues. A self-conscious person is
partly thinking about his problem and partly about what others think of
his performances. Diverted energy means loss of power and confusion of
ideas. Taking an attitude is by no means identical with being conscious
of one's attitude. The former is spontaneous, naive, and simple. It is
a sign of whole-souled relationship between a person and what he is
dealing with. The latter is not of necessity abnormal. It is sometimes
the easiest way of correcting a false method of approach, and of
improving the effectiveness of the means one is employing,—as golf
players, piano players, public speakers, etc., have occasionally to give
especial attention to their position and movements. But this need is
occasional and temporary. When it is effectual a person thinks of
himself in terms of what is to be done, as one means among others of the
realization of an end—as in the case of a tennis player practicing
to get the "feel" of a stroke. In abnormal cases, one thinks of himself
not as part of the agencies of execution, but as a separate
object—as when the player strikes an attitude thinking of the
impression it will make upon spectators, or is worried because of the
impression he fears his movements give rise to.
Confidence is a good name for what is intended by the term directness.
It should not be confused, however, with self-confidence which may be a
form of self-consciousness—or of "cheek." Confidence is not a name
for what one thinks or feels about his attitude it is not reflex. It
denotes the straightforwardness with which one goes at what he has to
do. It denotes not conscious trust in the efficacy of one's powers but
unconscious faith in the possibilities of the situation. It signifies
rising to the needs of the situation.
We have already pointed out (See p. 199)
the
objections to making students emphatically aware of the fact that they
are studying or learning. Just in the degree in which they are induced
by the conditions to be so aware, they are not studying and learning.
They are in a divided and complicated attitude. Whatever methods of a
teacher call a pupil's attention off from what he has to do and transfer
it to his own attitude towards what he is doing impair directness of concern
and action. Persisted in, the pupil acquires a permanent tendency to
fumble, to gaze about aimlessly, to look for some clew of action beside
that which the subject matter supplies. Dependence upon extraneous
suggestions and directions, a state of foggy confusion, take the place
of that sureness with which children (and grown-up people who have not
been sophisticated by "education") confront the situations of life.
2.
Open-mindedness. Partiality is, as we have seen, an accompaniment of
the existence of interest, since this means sharing, partaking, taking
sides in some movement. All the more reason, therefore, for an attitude
of mind which actively welcomes suggestions and relevant information
from all sides. In the chapter on Aims it was shown that foreseen ends
are factors in the development of a changing situation. They are the
means by which the direction of action is controlled. They are
subordinate to the situation, therefore, not the situation to them.
They are not ends in the sense of finalities to which everything must be
bent and sacrificed. They are, as foreseen, means of guiding the
development of a situation. A target is not the future goal of
shooting; it is the centering factor in a present shooting. Openness of
mind means accessibility of mind to any and every consideration that
will throw light upon the situation that needs to be cleared up, and
that will help determine the consequences of acting this way or that.
Efficiency in accomplishing ends which have been settled upon as
unalterable can coexist with a narrowly opened mind. But intellectual
growth means constant expansion of horizons and consequent formation of
new purposes and new responses. These are impossible without an active
disposition to welcome points of view hitherto alien; an active desire
to entertain considerations which modify existing purposes. Retention
of capacity to grow is the reward of such intellectual hospitality. The
worst thing about stubbornness of mind, about prejudices, is that they
arrest development; they shut the mind off from new stimuli.
Open-mindedness means retention of the childlike attitude;
closed-mindedness means premature intellectual old age.
Exorbitant desire for uniformity of procedure and for prompt external
results are the chief foes which the open-minded attitude meets in
school. The teacher who does not permit and encourage diversity of
operation in dealing with questions is imposing intellectual blinders
upon pupils—restricting their vision to the one path the teacher's
mind happens to approve. Probably the chief cause of devotion to
rigidity of method is, however, that it seems to promise speedy,
accurately measurable, correct results. The zeal for "answers" is the
explanation of much of the zeal for rigid and mechanical methods.
Forcing and overpressure have the same origin, and the same result upon
alert and varied intellectual interest.
Open-mindedness is not the same as empty-mindedness. To hang out a sign
saying "Come right in; there is no one at home" is not the equivalent of
hospitality. But there is a kind of passivity, willingness to let
experiences accumulate and sink in and ripen, which is an essential of
development. Results (external answers or solutions) may be hurried;
processes may not be forced. They take their own time to mature. Were
all instructors to realize that the quality of mental process, not the
production of correct answers, is the measure of educative growth
something hardly less than a revolution in teaching would be worked.
3.
Single-mindedness. So far as the word is concerned, much that was said
under the head of "directness" is applicable. But what the word is here
intended to convey is completeness of interest, unity of purpose; the
absence of suppressed but effectual ulterior aims for which the
professed aim is but a mask. It is equivalent to mental integrity.
Absorption, engrossment, full concern with subject matter for its own
sake, nurture it. Divided interest and evasion destroy it.
Intellectual integrity, honesty, and sincerity are at bottom not matters
of conscious purpose but of quality of active response. Their
acquisition is fostered of course by conscious intent, but
self-deception is very easy. Desires are urgent. When the demands and
wishes of others forbid their direct expression they are easily driven
into subterranean and deep channels. Entire surrender, and wholehearted
adoption of the course of action demanded by others are almost
impossible. Deliberate revolt or deliberate attempts to deceive others
may result. But the more frequent outcome is a confused and divided
state of interest in which one is fooled as to one's own real intent.
One tries to serve two masters at once. Social instincts, the strong
desire to please others and get their approval, social training, the
general sense of duty and of authority, apprehension of penalty, all
lead to a half-hearted effort to conform, to "pay attention to the
lesson," or whatever the requirement is. Amiable individuals want to do
what they are expected to do. Consciously the pupil thinks he is doing
this. But his own desires are not abolished. Only their evident
exhibition is suppressed. Strain of attention to what is hostile to
desire is irksome; in spite of one's conscious wish, the underlying
desires determine the main course of thought, the deeper emotional
responses. The mind wanders from the nominal subject and devotes itself
to what is intrinsically more desirable. A systematized divided
attention expressing the duplicity of the state of desire is the result.
One has only to recall his own experiences in school or at the present
time when outwardly employed in actions which do not engage one's
desires and purposes, to realize how prevalent is this attitude of
divided attention—double-mindedness. We are so used to it that we
take it for granted that a considerable amount of it is necessary. It
may be; if so, it is the more important to face its bad intellectual
effects. Obvious is the loss of energy of thought immediately available
when one is consciously trying (or trying to seem to try) to attend to
one matter, while unconsciously one's imagination is spontaneously going
out to more congenial affairs. More subtle and more permanently
crippling to efficiency of intellectual activity is a fostering of
habitual self-deception, with the confused sense of reality which
accompanies it. A double standard of reality, one for our own private
and more or less concealed interests, and another for public and
acknowledged concerns, hampers, in most of us, integrity and
completeness of mental action. Equally serious is the fact that a split
is set up between conscious thought and attention and impulsive blind
affection and desire. Reflective dealings with the material of
instruction is constrained and half-hearted; attention wanders. The
topics to which it wanders are unavowed and hence intellectually
illicit; transactions with them are furtive. The discipline that comes
from regulating response by deliberate inquiry having a purpose fails;
worse than that, the deepest concern and most congenial enterprises of
the imagination (since they center about the things dearest to desire)
are casual, concealed. They enter into action in ways which are
unacknowledged. Not subject to rectification by consideration of
consequences, they are demoralizing.
School conditions favorable to this division of mind between avowed,
public, and socially responsible undertakings, and private,
ill-regulated, and suppressed indulgences of thought are not hard to
find. What is sometimes called "stern discipline," i.e., external
coercive pressure, has this tendency. Motivation through rewards
extraneous to the thing to be done has a like effect. Everything that
makes schooling merely preparatory
(See ante, p. 64)
works in this direction. Ends being beyond the pupil's present grasp, other
agencies have to be found to procure immediate attention to assigned tasks.
Some responses are secured, but desires and affections not enlisted must
find other outlets. Not less serious is exaggerated emphasis upon drill
exercises designed to produce skill in action, independent of any
engagement of thought—exercises have no purpose but the production
of automatic skill. Nature abhors a mental vacuum. What do teachers
imagine is happening to thought and emotion when the latter get no
outlet in the things of immediate activity? Were they merely kept in
temporary abeyance, or even only calloused, it would not be a matter of
so much moment. But they are not abolished; they are not suspended;
they are not suppressed—save with reference to the task in
question. They follow their own chaotic and undisciplined course. What
is native, spontaneous, and vital in mental reaction goes unused and
untested, and the habits formed are such that these qualities become
less and less available for public and avowed ends.
4.
Responsibility. By responsibility as an element in intellectual
attitude is meant the disposition to consider in advance the probable
consequences of any projected step and deliberately to accept them: to
accept them in the sense of taking them into account, acknowledging them
in action, not yielding a mere verbal assent. Ideas, as we have seen,
are intrinsically standpoints and methods for bringing about a solution
of a perplexing situation; forecasts calculated to influence responses.
It is only too easy to think that one accepts a statement or believes a
suggested truth when one has not considered its implications; when one
has made but a cursory and superficial survey of what further things one
is committed to by acceptance. Observation and recognition, belief and
assent, then become names for lazy acquiescence in what is externally
presented.
It would be much better to have fewer facts and truths in
instruction—that is, fewer things supposedly accepted,—if a
smaller number of situations could be intellectually worked out to the
point where conviction meant something real—some identification of
the self with the type of conduct demanded by facts and foresight of
results. The most permanent bad results of undue complication of school
subjects and congestion of school studies and lessons are not the worry,
nervous strain, and superficial acquaintance that follow (serious as
these are), but the failure to make clear what is involved in really
knowing and believing a thing. Intellectual responsibility means severe
standards in this regard. These standards can be built up only through
practice in following up and acting upon the meaning of what is
acquired.
Intellectual thoroughness is thus another name for the attitude we
are considering. There is a kind of thoroughness which is almost purely
physical: the kind that signifies mechanical and exhausting drill upon
all the details of a subject. Intellectual thoroughness is seeing a
thing through. It depends upon a unity of purpose to which details are
subordinated, not upon presenting a multitude of disconnected details.
It is manifested in the firmness with which the full meaning of the
purpose is developed, not in attention, however "conscientious" it may
be, to the steps of action externally imposed and directed.
Summary.
—Method is a statement of the way the subject matter of an
experience develops most effectively and fruitfully. It is derived,
accordingly, from observation of the course of experiences where there
is no conscious distinction of personal attitude and manner from
material dealt with. The assumption that method is something separate
is connected with the notion of the isolation of mind and self from the
world of things. It makes instruction and learning formal, mechanical,
constrained. While methods are individualized, certain features of the
normal course of an experience to its fruition may be discriminated,
because of the fund of wisdom derived from prior experiences and because
of general similarities in the materials dealt with from time to time.
Expressed in terms of the attitude of the individual the traits of good
method are straightforwardness, flexible intellectual interest or
open-minded will to learn, integrity of purpose, and acceptance of
responsibility for the consequences of one's activity including thought.
Footnotes
[[9]]
This point is developed below in a discussion of what
are termed psychological and logical methods respectively. See p.
219.