VI. RECENT AND CURRENT VIEWS
A shallow reflection of Schiller's views is found in
Herbert Spencer, who
vaguely remembers reading
about the play theory in some German author
whose
name escaped him. While what he has to say has little
bearing on
art, it is included in a simple version of
the “surplus
energy” theory:
We find that time and strength are not wholly absorbed
in providing
for immediate needs... Hence play of all
kinds—hence the
tendency to superfluous and useless ex-
ercise of faculties that have been quiescent
(Spencer
[1870-72]).
About the turn of this century there was a significant
revival of interest
in the topic of play, with some
bearing on art. Karl Groos' two books
chiefly rely on
the role of imitation, empathy, and education in the
learning and socialization process:
... play leads from what is easy to more difficult tasks,
since only
deliberate conquest can produce the feeling of
pleasure in
success
(1901, p. 8).
Lange, who follows Groos fairly closely, stresses the
structure of
self-imposed rules which call for the exer-
cise of imagination. He opposes the passivity of the
spectator to
the activity of the creator, and extends
his argument from play to art in
pointing to the inven-
tion of a context
developed in the course of creation
of a work of art.
Of the many commentaries on the surplus energy
and education theories a few
examples may be cited.
Dessoir (pp. 318ff.) treats the Kant-Schiller
approaches
favorably and with great penetration. Croce (p. 83),
followed by Collingwood, accepts the “freedom from
causality” argument of Schiller as “possible,”
but finds
the surplus energy argument, especially as found in
Spencer
“outrageous.” Guyau, on the other hand (p.
174),
accepts the latter argument, but sees “art as too
involved with
life to be mere play.” And Huizinga,
whose splendid book goes
much beyond our scope here,
treats Schiller quite harshly (p. 168), having
evidently
misunderstood his case.
A lengthy literature from the utopian socialists to
the 1960's expands the
leisure theory to incorporate
art and play into the activities appropriate
to an in-
creasingly affluent society. The
education theories are
currently in the uncertain stewardship of the
schools
of education and the learning psychologists; a stagger-
ing array of studies pursue the
related problems of
value-free finger-painting and learning by playing
in
a manner that has gone far to discredit the whole
argument.
The metaphysical and psychological theories remain
worthy of serious
consideration. As to the first there
has been a significant tendency to
extend creativity,
innovation, conventional (self-imposed) rule-making
as
obvious features of play and art beyond these to scien-
tific and even to cosmological explanations. Charles
S.
Peirce, who acknowledges his debt to Friedrich Schiller
(p. 401),
develops (pp. 360f.) a notion of free aesthetic
contemplation—“Pure
Play”—culminating in “Muse-
ment” concerning “some wonder in
one of the Uni-
verses.” Koestler
(1964, especially pp. 509ff.) displays
the interconnectedness of humor,
art, and science with
a wealth of illustration. But the most succinct
statement
in recent literature on the subject is found in Kroeber
(1948, p. 357):
Generically, all the discoveries and innovations of pure
science and
fine art—those intellectual and aesthetic pur-
suits which are carried on without reference to
technology
or utility—may be credited to functioning of the
human
play impulses.... They rest on the play impulse, which
is
connected with growth but is dissociated from preser-
vation, comfort, or utility, and which in science
and art
is translated into the realm of imagination, abstraction,
relations, and sensuous form.
Finally, there is another area, almost too vague to
document precisely, but
pervasive enough in recent
decades, in which certain childlike qualities
(including
playfulness) are assimilated to some desirable features
of
art. While its origins may be traced back to Plato
at least, the
combination is modern, especially in its
emphasis on the unconscious nature
of creativity. If,
as Ellen Key argued in her famous book, this is The
Century of the Child (1909), much that is
relevant to
our theme will be displayed in what George Boas has
called
The Cult of Childhood (1966). Emphasis is laid
on the child's naiveté, spontaneity, and unconscious-
ness, and on the self-absorption of the child's
activi-
ties—these are
preferred to the calculation and pur-
posiveness of adult behavior. The child's vision is taken
to be
innocent, fresh, unencumbered by conceptual
fixity or subordination to
cognitive or moral criteria.
The artist (e.g., Rilke, Klee) is seen as
liberated from
the exigencies either of representationalism in content
or of set formal patterns. It would be a mistake to insist
that all aspects
of this shift in aesthetic objectives are
connected with nostalgia for
childlike simplicity and
still less with play. In part it must be
associated rather
will the metaphysical anarchy currently fashionable
and that dates from some of the post-Kantian develop-
ments we have traced. Among relevant contemporary
positions in aesthetics mention must be made at least
of Freudian
psychology and proponents of “aesthetic
surface.”
An important paper of Freud's, “Creative Writers
and
Day-Dreaming,” associates imagination, creativity,
and play, and
draws on a parallelism between the child
and the writer, each of whom
creates a world of his
own. This world is taken seriously, for the
opposite
of play is not the serious but the real. (Freud makes
the
further point that this play is not wholly uncon-
nected with the real, otherwise we have fantasy not
play.) From
this it follows that features of the real
world are rearranged by the child
in his play and by
the artist in his creation. The difference between
these
and day-dreaming is that the latter entails a degree
of
wish-fulfilment that moves in the direction of neuro-
sis or psychosis; but the differences appear to be of
degree not
kind: “... a piece of creative writing, like
a day-dream, is a
continuation of, and a substitute for,
what was once the play of
childhood.” The elaboration
of these insights by the various
psychoanalytic schools,
particularly by Jung and Rank, is immensely
detailed.
And it is but a step from these to a great variety of
perspectives advanced by existentialist and phenome-
nological writers on aesthetics who make a great
deal
of the “child's vision.”
This brings us close to the notion of “aesthetic sur-
face” (D. W. Prall, Aesthetic
Analysis, New York,
1929) and “sheer appearance” (S. Langer, Philosophy
in a New Key..., Cambridge, Mass., 1942).
Again,
the emphasis here is on the avoidance of conceptual
rigidity,
allowing the object to speak to imagination,
a playing with the possible
things the aesthetic object
might be, as in Dada for example. These
illustrate the
tendency in art and play for forms and structures to
be
explored and exploited more than the specific con-
tent of the artwork or game; much is made of the
paradoxical status
of “commitment” in the sense that
play and aesthetic
experience are contemplative, i.e.,
they do not require that what is
encountered be trans-
lated into action, yet
they furnish a rich stock of
paradigm situations in largely vicarious
experience that
is in fact deployed where knowledge and action are
called for. The “high seriousness” of play and
aesthetic
immersion is one of the ways in which many thinkers
have
tried to give expression to this phenomenon; and
it derives from the dual
capacity of art to be directly
an end-in-itself yet indirectly a means to
irrelevant or
seemingly opposed ends.