University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
Dictionary of the History of Ideas

Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas
2 occurrences of Ancients and Moderns in the Eighteenth Century
[Clear Hits]
  
  
expand section 
  
expand section 
  
  

expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
collapse sectionIII. 
  
  
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 

2 occurrences of Ancients and Moderns in the Eighteenth Century
[Clear Hits]

II

The history of early Greek cosmology is largely the
history of the interpretation of the cosmos in terms
of various ideas derived from the three fields of politics,
biology, and technology. Aristotle, especially, criticized
many such ideas, as for example the belief that such
substances as air or fire are alive. Yet these three types
of images continued to be influential long after him.
The Stoics, in particular, not only represented the
cosmos as a living creature and believed in the pur-
poseful, craftsmanlike activity of Nature, but also
described the world as a state governed by divine law,
and similar ideas had a long history in the Middle Ages
and in the Renaissance.

Moreover while Greek cosmology owed many ideas
to politics and biology, Greek biological theories and
political thought were similarly colored by the use of
images drawn from one another. For example, the twin
ideas that health depends on the equality of rights
(ἰσονομία) of opposed powers in the body, and that
disease results from the supreme rule (μοναρχία) of one
such power, go back to Alcmaeon and thereafter be-
come commonplaces of Greek pathology and thera-
peutics. Aristotle, too, compares the living creature
with a well-governed city, describing the heart as the
central seat of authority in the body (e.g., De motu
animalium
703a 29ff.).

Conversely Greek political theorists sometimes
compare the state with a living organism, and the
influence of other biological and technological analo-
gies on Greek ethics is marked. Here Plato provides
the best examples. First he constructed an elaborate
analogy between the state and the individual in the
Republic, suggesting, for instance, that both may be
divided into three parts, one of which—the Guardians
in the state and reason in the soul—should be in overall
control. A second important analogy in Plato is that
between justice and health. This provides the main
grounds for the two theses, (1) that the just man is
happier than the unjust, and (2) that once having done
wrong, it is better to suffer than to escape punish-
ment—for punishment is the “cure” for injustice. And
a third recurrent analogy is that between the politician
and the artist or craftsman, where Plato suggests that
the statesman must be an expert in politics in a way
comparable with that in which a pilot is expert in
navigation or a doctor in medicine. We find similar
types of analogies in Aristotle, too. In the Politics (1295a
40f.) he describes the constitution as the life, as it were,
of the state, and in the Nicomachean Ethics (1113a
25ff.) he draws a comparison between the good man
and the healthy: just as a sick person may be mistaken
about what is hot or cold or sweet or bitter, and the
judge of these things is the normal, healthy man, so,
he argues, the good man (ὁ σπουδαῖος) is the judge of
what is right and wrong.

Greek ideas on nature and art, on the state, the living
organism, and the world as a whole, are linked by a
series of interlocking analogies. Most of the major fifth-
and fourth-century philosophers put forward analogies
of one or other of the types we have considered. Yet
the particular forms that their analogies take are very
varied, and no single version of any of them dominates
the period. Had any such orthodoxy existed, these
analogies might have impeded the development of
certain inquiries far more than they did. As it was,


063

although some Hippocratic writers produced elaborate
versions of the microcosm-macrocosm analogy, this did
not prevent other theorists from making considerable
progress in both the study of anatomy and in astron-
omy, during the fourth century. Again, both Plato and
Aristotle held that the stars are alive and divine, al-
though this had been denied by such thinkers as
Anaxagoras; yet this belief did not prevent Aristotle
from attempting a detailed mechanical account of the
movements of the heavenly bodies, based on Eudoxus'
theory of concentric spheres.