7.
CHAPTER VII
THE DEMOCRATIC CONCEPTION IN EDUCATION:
For the most part, save incidentally, we have hitherto been concerned with
education as it may exist in any social group. We have now to make explicit
the differences in the spirit, material, and method of education as it operates
in different types of community life. To say that education is a social
function, securing direction and development in the immature through their
participation in the life of the group to which they belong, is to say
in effect that education will vary with the quality of life which
prevails in a group. Particularly is it true that a society which not
only changes but-which has the ideal of such change as will improve it,
will have different standards and methods of education from one which
aims simply at the perpetuation of its own customs. To make the general
ideas set forth applicable to our own educational practice, it is,
therefore, necessary to come to closer quarters with the nature of
present social life.
1. The Implications of Human Association.
—Society is one word, but many things. Men associate together in
all kinds of ways and for all kinds of purposes. One man is concerned
in a multitude of diverse groups, in which his associates may be quite
different. It often seems as if they had nothing in common except that
they are modes of associated life. Within every larger social
organization there are numerous minor groups: not only political
subdivisions, but industrial, scientific, religious, associations.
There are political parties with differing aims, social sets, cliques,
gangs, corporations, partnerships, groups bound closely together by ties
of blood, and so on in endless variety. In many modern states and in
some ancient, there is great diversity of populations, of varying
languages, religions, moral codes, and traditions. From this
standpoint, many a minor political unit, one of our large cities, for
example, is a congeries of loosely associated societies, rather than an
inclusive and permeating community of action and thought.
(See Ante, p. 24.)
The terms society, community, are thus ambiguous. They have both a
eulogistic or normative sense, and a descriptive sense; a meaning
de jure and a meaning
de facto. In social philosophy, the
former connotation is almost always uppermost. Society is conceived as one
by its very nature. The qualities which accompany this unity, praiseworthy
community of purpose and welfare, loyalty to public ends, mutuality of
sympathy, are emphasized. But when we look at the facts which the term
denotes instead of confining our attention to its intrinsic
connotation, we find not unity, but a plurality of societies, good
and bad. Men banded together in a criminal conspiracy, business aggregations
that prey upon the public while serving it, political machines held together
by the interest of plunder, are included. If it is said that such
organizations are not societies because they do not meet the ideal
requirements of the notion of society, the answer, in part, is that the
conception of society is then made so "ideal" as to be of no use, having
no reference to facts; and in part, that each of these organizations, no
matter how opposed to the interests of other groups, has something of
the praiseworthy qualities of "Society" which hold it together. There
is honor among thieves, and a band of robbers has a common interest as
respects its members. Gangs are marked by fraternal feeling, and narrow
cliques by intense loyalty to their own codes. Family life may be
marked by exclusiveness, suspicion, and jealousy as to those without,
and yet be a model of amity and mutual aid within. Any education given
by a group tends to socialize its members, but the quality and value of
the socialization depends upon the habits and aims of the group.
Hence, once more, the need of a measure for the worth of any given mode
of social life. In seeking this measure, we have to avoid two extremes.
We cannot set up, out of our heads, something we regard as an ideal
society. We must base our conception upon societies which actually
exist, in order to have any assurance that our ideal is a practicable
one. But, as we have just seen, the ideal cannot simply repeat the
traits which are actually found. The problem is to extract the
desirable traits of forms of community life which actually exist, and
employ them to criticize undesirable features and suggest improvement.
Now in any social group whatever, even in a gang of thieves, we find
some interest held in common, and we find a certain amount of
interaction and coöperative intercourse with other groups. From these
two traits we derive our standard. How numerous and varied are the
interests which are consciously shared? How full and free is the
interplay with other forms of association? If we apply these
considerations to, say, a criminal band, we find that the ties which
consciously hold the members together are few in number, reducible
almost to a common interest in plunder; and that they are of such a
nature as to isolate the group from other groups with respect to give
and take of the values of life. Hence, the education such a society
gives is partial and distorted. If we take, on the other hand, the kind
of family life which illustrates the standard, we find that there are
material, intellectual, aæsthetic interests in which all participate and
that the progress of one member has worth for the experience of other
members—it is readily communicable—and that the family is
not an isolated whole, but enters intimately into relationships with
business groups, with schools, with all the agencies of culture, as well
as with other similar groups, and that it plays a due part in the
political organization and in return receives support from it. In
short, there are many interests consciously communicated and shared; and
there are varied and free points of contact with other modes of
association.
I. Let us apply the first element in this criterion to a despotically
governed state. It is not true there is no common interest in such an
organization between governed and governors. The authorities in command
must make some appeal to the native activities of the subjects, must
call some of their powers into play. Talleyrand said that a government
could do everything with bayonets except sit on them. This cynical
declaration is at least a recognition that the bond of union is not
merely one of coercive force. It may be said, however, that the
activities appealed to are themselves unworthy and degrading—that
such a government calls into functioning activity simply capacity for
fear. In a way, this statement is true. But it overlooks the fact that
fear need not be an undesirable factor in experience. Caution,
circumspection, prudence, desire to foresee future events so as to avert
what is harmful, these desirable traits are as much a product of calling
the impulse of fear into play as is cowardice and abject submission.
The real difficulty is that the appeal to fear is isolated. In evoking
dread and hope of specific tangible reward—say comfort and
ease—many other capacities are left untouched. Or rather, they
are affected, but in such a way as to pervert them. Instead of
operating on their own account they are reduced to mere servants of
attaining pleasure and avoiding pain.
This is equivalent to saying that there is no extensive number of common
interests; there is no free play back and forth among the members of the
social group. Stimulation and response are exceedingly one-sided. In
order to have a large number of values in common, all the members of the
group must have an equable opportunity to receive and to take from
others. There must be a large variety of shared undertakings and
experiences. Otherwise, the influences which educate some into masters,
educate others into slaves. And the experience of each party loses in
meaning, when the free interchange of varying modes of life-experience
is arrested. A separation into a privileged and a subject-class
prevents social endosmosis. The evils thereby affecting the superior
class are less material and less perceptible, but equally real. Their
culture tends to be sterile, to be turned back to feed on itself; their
art becomes a showy display and artificial; their wealth luxurious;
their knowledge overspecialized; their manners fastidious rather than
humane.
Lack of the free and equitable intercourse which springs from a variety
of shared interests makes intellectual stimulation unbalanced.
Diversity of stimulation means novelty, and novelty means challenge to
thought. The more activity is restricted to a few definite
lines—as it is when there are rigid class lines preventing
adequate interplay of experiences—the more action tends to become
routine on the part of the class at a disadvantage, and capricious,
aimless, and explosive on the part of the class having the materially
fortunate position. Plato defined a slave as one who accepts from
another the purposes which control his conduct. This condition obtains
even where there is no slavery in the legal sense. It is found wherever
men are engaged in activity which is socially serviceable, but whose
service they do not understand and have no personal interest in. Much
is said about scientific management of work. It is a narrow view which
restricts the science which secures efficiency of operation to movements
of the muscles. The chief opportunity for science is the discovery of
the relations of a man to his work—including his relations to
others who take part—which will enlist his intelligent interest in
what he is doing. Efficiency in production often demands division of
labor. But it is reduced to a mechanical routine unless workers see the
technical, intellectual, and social relationships involved in what they
do, and engage in their work because of the motivation furnished by such
perceptions. The tendency to reduce such things as efficiency of
activity and scientific management to purely technical externals is
evidence of the one-sided stimulation of thought given to those in
control of industry—those who supply its aims. Because of their
lack of all-round and well-balanced social interest, there is not
sufficient stimulus for attention to the human factors and relationships
in industry. Intelligence is narrowed to the factors concerned with
technical production and marketing of goods. No doubt, a very acute and
intense intelligence in these narrow lines can be developed, but the
failure to take into account the significant social factors means none
the less an absence of mind, and a corresponding distortion of emotional
life.
II. This illustration (whose point is to be extended to all
associations lacking reciprocity of interest) brings us to our second
point. The isolation and exclusiveness of a gang or clique brings its
antisocial spirit into relief. But this same spirit is found wherever
one group has interests "of its own" which shut it out from full
interaction with other groups, so that its prevailing purpose is the
protection of what it has got, instead of reorganization and progress
through wider relationships. It marks nations in their isolation from
one another; families which seclude their domestic concerns as if they
had no connection with a larger life; schools when separated from the
interest of home and community; the divisions of rich and poor; learned
and unlearned. The essential point is that isolation makes for rigidity
and formal institutionalizing of life, for static and selfish ideals
within the group. That savage tribes regard aliens and enemies as
synonymous is not accidental. It springs from the fact that they have
identified their experience with rigid adherence to their past customs.
On such a basis it is wholly logical to fear intercourse with others,
for such contact might dissolve custom. It would certainly occasion
reconstruction. It is a commonplace that an alert and expanding mental
life depends upon an enlarging range of contact with the physical
environment. But the principle applies even more significantly to the
field where we are apt to ignore it—the sphere of social contacts.
Every expansive era in the history of mankind has coincided with the
operation of factors which have tended to eliminate distance between
peoples and classes previously hemmed off from one another. Even the
alleged benefits of war, so far as more than alleged, spring from the
fact that conflict of peoples at least enforces intercourse between them
and thus accidentally enables them to learn from one another, and
thereby to expand their horizons. Travel, economic and commercial
tendencies, have at present gone far to break down external barriers; to
bring peoples and classes into closer and more perceptible connection
with one another. It remains for the most part to secure the
intellectual and emotional significance of this physical annihilation of
space.
2. The Democratic Ideal.
—The two elements in our criterion both point to democracy. The
first signifies not only more numerous and more varied points of shared
common interest, but greater reliance upon the recognition of mutual
interests as a factor in social control. The second means not only
freer interaction between social groups ( once isolated so far as
intention could keep up a separation ) but change in social
habit—its continuous readjustment through meeting the new
situations produced by varied intercourse. And these two traits are
precisely what characterize the democratically constituted society.
Upon the educational side, we note first that the realization of a form
of social life in which interests are mutually interpenetrating, and
where progress, or readjustment, is an important consideration, makes a
democratic community more interested than other communities have cause
to be in deliberate and systematic education. The devotion of democracy
to education is a familiar fact. The superficial explanation is that a
government resting upon popular suffrage cannot be successful unless
those who elect and who obey their governors are educated. Since a
democratic society repudiates the principle of external authority, it
must find a substitute in voluntary disposition and interest; these can
be created only by education. But there is a deeper explanation. A
democracy is more than a form of government; it is primarily a mode of
associated living, of conjoint communicated experience. The extension
in space of the number of individuals who participate in an interest so
that each has to refer his own action to that of others, and to consider
the action of others to give point and direction to his own, is
equivalent to the breaking down of those barriers of class, race, and
national territory which kept men from perceiving the full import of
their activity. These more numerous and more varied points of contact
denote a greater diversity of stimuli to which an individual has to
respond; they consequently put a premium on variation in his action.
They secure a liberation of powers which remain suppressed as long as
the incitations to action are partial, as they must be in a group which
in its exclusiveness shuts out many interests.
The widening of the area of shared concerns, and the liberation of a
greater diversity of personal capacities which characterize a democracy,
are not of course the product of deliberation and conscious effort. On
the contrary, they were caused by the development of modes of
manufacture and commerce, travel, migration, and intercommunication
which flowed from the command of science over natural energy. But after
greater individualization on one hand, and a broader community of
interest on the other have come into existence, it is a matter of
deliberate effort to sustain and extend them. Obviously a society to
which stratification into separate classes would be fatal, must see to
it that intellectual opportunities are accessible to all on equable and
easy terms. A society marked off into classes need he specially
attentive only to the education of its ruling elements. A society which
is mobile, which is full of channels for the distribution of a change
occurring anywhere, must see to it that its members are educated to
personal initiative and adaptability. Otherwise, they will be
overwhelmed by the changes in which they are caught and whose
significance or connections they do not perceive. The result will be a
confusion in which a few will appropriate to themselves the results of
the blind and externally directed activities of others.
3. The Platonic Educational Philosophy.
—Subsequent chapters will be devoted to making explicit the
implications of the democratic ideas in education. In the remaining
portions of this chapter, we shall consider the educational theories
which have been evolved in three epochs when the social import of
education was especially conspicuous. The first one to be considered is
that of Plato. No one could better express than did he the fact that a
society is stably organized when each individual is doing that for which
he has aptitude by nature in such a way as to be useful to others (or to
contribute to the whole to which he belongs ); and that it is the
business of education to discover these aptitudes and progressively to
train them for social use. Much which has been said so far is borrowed
from what Plato first consciously taught the world. But conditions
which he could not intellectually control led him to restrict these
ideas in their application. He never got any conception of the
indefinite plurality of activities which may characterize an individual
and a social group, and consequently limited his view to a limited
number of classes of capacities and of social arrangements.
Plato's starting point is that the organization of society depends
ultimately upon knowledge of the end of existence. If we do not know
its end, we shall be at the mercy of accident and caprice. Unless we
know the end, the good, we shall have no criterion for rationally
deciding what the possibilities are which should be promoted, nor how
social arrangements are to be ordered. We shall have no conception of
the proper limits and distribution of activities—what he called
justice—as a trait of both individual and social organization.
But how is the knowledge of the final and permanent good to be achieved?
In dealing with this question we come upon the seemingly insuperable
obstacle that such knowledge is not possible save in a just and
harmonious social order. Everywhere else the mind is distracted and
misled by false valuations and false perspectives. A disorganized and
factional society sets up a number of different models and standards.
Under such conditions it is impossible for the individual to attain
consistency of mind. Only a complete whole is fully self-consistent. A
society which rests upon the supremacy of some factor over another
irrespective of its rational or proportionate claims, inevitably leads
thought astray. It puts a premium on certain things and slurs over
others, and creates a mind whose seeming unity is forced and distorted.
Education proceeds ultimately from the patterns furnished by
institutions, customs, and laws. Only in a just state will these be
such as to give the right education; and only those who have rightly
trained minds will be able to recognize the end, and ordering principle
of things. We seem to be caught in a hopeless circle. However, Plato
suggested a way out. A few men, philosophers or lovers of
wisdom—or truth—may by study learn at least in outline the
proper patterns of true existence. If a powerful ruler should form a
state after these patterns, then its regulations could be preserved. An
education could be given which would sift individuals, discovering what
they were good for, and supplying a method of assigning each to the work
in life for which his nature fits him. Each doing his own part, and
never transgressing, the order and unity of the whole would be
maintained.
It would be impossible to find in any scheme of philosophic thought a
more adequate recognition on one hand of the educational significance of
social arrangements and, on the other, of the dependence of those
arrangements upon the means used to educate the young. It would be
impossible to find a deeper sense of the function of education in
discovering and developing personal capacities, and training them so
that they would connect with the activities of others. Yet the society
in which the theory was propounded was so undemocratic that Plato could
not work out a solution for the problem whose terms he clearly saw.
While he affirmed with emphasis that the place of the individual in
society should not be determined by birth or wealth or any conventional
status, but by his own nature as discovered in the process of education,
he had no perception of the uniqueness of individuals. For him they
fall by nature into classes, and into a very small number of classes at
that. Consequently the testing and sifting function of education only
shows to which one of three classes an individual belongs. There being
no recognition that each individual constitutes his own class, there
could be no recognition of the infinite diversity of active tendencies
and combinations of tendencies of which an individual is capable. There
were only three types of faculties or powers in the individual's
constitution. Hence education would soon reach a static limit in each
class, for only diversity makes change and progress.
In some individuals, appetites naturally dominate; they are assigned to
the laboring and trading class, which expresses and supplies human
wants. Others reveal, upon education, that over and above appetites,
they have a generous, outgoing, assertively courageous disposition.
They become the citizen-subjects of the state; its defenders in war; its
internal guardians in peace. But their limit is fixed by their lack of
reason, which is a capacity to grasp the universal. Those who possess
this are capable of the highest kind of education, and become in time
the legislators of the state—for laws are the universals which
control the particulars of experience. Thus it is not true that in
intent, Plato subordinated the individual to the social whole. But it
is true that lacking the perception of the uniqueness of every
individual, his incommensurability with others, and consequently not
recognizing that a society might change and yet be stable, his doctrine
of limited powers and classes came in net effect to the idea of the
subordination of individuality.
We cannot better Plato's conviction that an individual is happy and
society well organized when each individual engages in those activities
for which he has a natural equipment, nor his conviction that it is the
primary office of education to discover this equipment to its possessor
and train him for its effective use. But progress in knowledge has made
us aware of the superficiality of Plato's lumping of individuals and
their original powers into a few sharply marked-off classes; it has
taught us that original capacities are indefinitely numerous and
variable. It is but the other side of this fact to say that in the
degree in which society has become democratic, social organization means
utilization of the specific and variable qualities of individuals, not
stratification by classes. Although his educational philosophy was
revolutionary, it was none the less in bondage to static ideals. He
thought that change or alteration was evidence of lawless flux; that
true reality was unchangeable. Hence while he would radically change
the existing state of society, his aim was to construct a state in which
change would subsequently have no place. The final end of life is
fixed; given a state framed with this end in view, not even minor
details are to be altered. Though they might not be inherently
important, yet if permitted they would inure the minds of men to the
idea of change, and hence be dissolving and anarchic. The breakdown of
his philosophy is made apparent in the fact that he could not trust to
gradual improvements in education to bring about a better society which
should then improve education, and so on indefinitely. Correct
education could not come into existence until an ideal state existed,
and after that education would be devoted simply to its conservation.
For the existence of this state he was obliged to trust to some happy
accident by which philosophic wisdom should happen to coincide with
possession of ruling power in the state.
4. The "Individualistic" Ideal of the Eighteenth Century.
—In the eighteenth-century philosophy we find ourselves in a very
different circle of ideas. "Nature" still means something antithetical
to existing social organization; Plato exercised a great influence upon
Rousseau. But the voice of nature now speaks for the diversity of
individual talent and for the need of free development of individuality
in all its variety. Education in accord with nature furnishes the goal
and the method of instruction and discipline. Moreover, the native or
original endowment was conceived, in extreme cases, as nonsocial or even
as antisocial. Social arrangements were thought of as mere external
expedients by which these nonsocial individuals might secure a greater
amount of private happiness for themselves.
Nevertheless, these statements convey only an inadequate idea of the
true significance of the movement. In reality its chief interest was in
progress and in social progress. The seeming antisocial philosophy was
a somewhat transparent mask for an impetus toward a wider and freer
society—toward cosmopolitanism. The positive ideal was humanity.
In membership in humanity, as distinct from a state, man's capacities
would be liberated; while in existing political organizations his powers
were hampered and distorted to meet the requirements and selfish
interests of the rulers of the state. The doctrine of extreme
individualism was but the counterpart, the obverse, of ideals of the
indefinite perfectibility of man and of a social organization having a
scope as wide as humanity. The emancipated individual was to become the
organ and agent of a comprehensive and progressive society.
The heralds of this gospel were acutely conscious of the evils of the
social estate in which they found themselves. They attributed these
evils to the limitations imposed upon the free powers of man. Such
limitation was both distorting and corrupting. Their impassioned
devotion to emancipation of life from external restrictions which
operated to the exclusive advantage of the class to whom a past feudal
system consigned power, found intellectual formulation in a worship of
nature. To give "nature" full swing was to replace an artificial,
corrupt, and inequitable social order by a new and better kingdom of
humanity. Unrestrained faith in Nature as both a model and a working
power was strengthened by the advances of natural science. Inquiry
freed from prejudice and artificial restraints of church and state had
revealed that the world is a scene of law. The Newtonian solar system,
which expressed the reign of natural law, was a scene of wonderful
harmony, where every force balanced with every other.
Natural law would accomplish the same result in human relations, if men
would only get rid of the artificial man-imposed coercive
restrictions.
Education in accord with nature was thought to be the first step in
insuring this more social society. It was plainly seen that economic
and political limitations were ultimately dependent upon limitations of
thought and feeling. The first step in freeing men from external chains
was to emancipate them from the internal chains of false beliefs and
ideals. What was called social life, existing institutions, were too
false and corrupt to be intrusted with this work.
How could it be expected to undertake it when the undertaking meant its
own destruction? "Nature" must then be the power to which the enterprise
was to be left. Even the extreme sensationalistic theory of knowledge
which was current derived itself from this conception. To insist that
mind is originally passive and empty was one way of glorifying the
possibilities of education. If the mind was a wax tablet to be written
upon by objects, there were no limits to the possibility of education by
means of the natural environment. And since the natural world of
objects is a scene of harmonious "truth," this education would
infallibly produce minds filled with the truth.
5. Education as National and as Social.
—As soon as the first enthusiasm for freedom waned, the weakness
of the theory upon the constructive side became obvious. Merely to
leave everything to nature was, after all, but to negate the very idea
of education; it was to trust to the accidents of circumstance. Not
only was some method required but also some positive organ, some
administrative agency for carrying on the process of instruction. The
"complete and harmonious development of all powers," having as its
social counterpart an enlightened and progressive humanity, required
definite organization for its realization. Private individuals here and
there could proclaim the gospel; they could not execute the work. A
Pestalozzi could try experiments and exhort philanthropically inclined
persons having wealth and power to follow his example. But even
Pestalozzi saw that any effective pursuit of the new educational ideal
required the support of the state. The realization of the new education
destined to produce a new society was, after all, dependent upon the
activities of existing states. The movement for the democratic idea
inevitably became a movement for publicly conducted and administered
schools.
So far as Europe was concerned, the historic situation identified the
movement for a state-supported education with the nationalistic movement
in political life—a fact of incalculable significance for
subsequent movements. Under the influence of German thought in
particular, education became a civic function and the civic function was
identified with the realization of the ideal of the national state. The
"state" was substituted for humanity; cosmopolitanism gave way to
nationalism. To form the citizen, not the "man," became the aim of
education.
[5]
The historic situation to which reference is made is the after-effects
of the Napoleonic conquests, especially in Germany. The German states
felt (and subsequent events demonstrate the correctness of the belief )
that systematic attention to education was the best means of recovering
and maintaining their political integrity and power. Externally they
were weak and divided. Under the leadership of Prussian statesmen they
made this condition a stimulus to the development of an extensive and
thoroughly grounded system of public education.
This change in practice necessarily brought about a change in theory.
The individualistic theory receded into the background. The state
furnished not only the instrumentalities of public education but also
its goal. When the actual practice was such that the school system,
from the elementary grades through the university faculties, supplied
the patriotic citizen and soldier and the future state official and
administrator and furnished the means for military, industrial, and
political defense and expansion, it was impossible for theory not to
emphasize the aim of social efficiency. And with the immense importance
attached to the nationalistic state, surrounded by other competing and
more or less hostile states, it was equally impossible to interpret
social efficiency in terms of a vague cosmopolitan humanitarianism.
Since the maintenance of a particular national sovereignty required
subordination of individuals to the superior interests of the state both
in military defense and in struggles for international supremacy in
commerce, social efficiency was understood to imply a like
subordination. The educational process was taken to be one of
disciplinary training rather than of personal development. Since,
however, the ideal of culture as complete development of personality
persisted, educational philosophy attempted a reconciliation of the two
ideas. The reconciliation took the form of the conception of the
"organic" character of the state. The individual in his isolation is
nothing; only in and through an absorption of the aims and meaning of
organized institutions does he attain true personality. What appears to
be his subordination to political authority and the demand for sacrifice
of himself to the commands of his superiors is in reality but making his
own the objective reason manifested in the state—the only way in
which he can become truly rational. The notion of development which we
have seen to be characteristic of institutional idealism (as in the
Hegelian philosophy) was just such a deliberate effort to combine the
two ideas of complete realization of personality and thoroughgoing
"disciplinary" subordination to existing institutions.
The extent of the transformation of educational philosophy which
occurred in Germany in the generation occupied by the struggle against
Napoleon for national independence, may be gathered from Kant, who well
expresses the earlier individual-cosmopolitan ideal. In his treatise on
Pedagogics, consisting of lectures given in the later years of the
eighteenth century, he defines education as the process by which man
becomes man. Mankind begins its history submerged in nature—not
as Man who is a creature of reason, while nature furnishes only instinct
and appetite. Nature offers simply the germs which education is to
develop and perfect. The peculiarity of truly human life is that man
has to create himself by his own voluntary efforts; he has to make
himself a truly moral, rational, and free being. This creative effort
is carried on by the educational activities of slow generations. Its
acceleration depends upon men consciously striving to educate their
successors not for the existing state of affairs but so as to make
possible a future better humanity. But there is the great difficulty.
Each generation is inclined to educate its young so as to get along in
the present world instead of with a view to the proper end of education:
the promotion of the best possible realization of humanity as humanity.
Parents educate their children so that they may get on; princes educate
their subjects as instruments of their own purposes.
Who, then, shall conduct education so that humanity may improve? We must
depend upon the efforts of enlightened men in their private capacity.
"All culture begins with private men and spreads outward from them.
Simply through the efforts of persons of enlarged inclinations, who are
capable of grasping the ideal of a future better condition, is the
gradual approximation of human nature to its end possible.... Rulers
are simply interested in such training as will make their subjects
better tools for their own intentions." Even the subsidy by rulers of
privately conducted schools must be carefully safeguarded. For the
rulers' interest in the welfare of their own nation instead of in what
is best for humanity, will make them, if they give money for the
schools, wish to draw their plans. We have in this view an express
statement of the points characteristic of the eighteenth century
individualistic cosmopolitanism. The full development of private
personality is identified with the aims of humanity as a whole and with
the idea of progress. In addition we have an explicit fear of the
hampering influence of a state-conducted and state-regulated education
upon the attainment of these ideas. But in less than two decades after
this time, Kant's philosophic successors, Fichte and Hegel, elaborated
the idea that the chief function of the state is educational; that in
particular the regeneration of Germany is to be accomplished by an
education carried on in the interests of the state, and that the private
individual is of necessity an egoistic, irrational being, enslaved to
his appetites and to circumstances unless he submits voluntarily to the
educative discipline of state institutions and laws. In this spirit,
Germany was the first country to undertake a public, universal, and
compulsory system of education extending from the primary school through
the university, and to submit to jealous state regulation and
supervision all private educational enterprises.
Two results should stand out from this brief historical survey. The
first is that such terms as the individual and the social conceptions of
education are quite meaningless taken at large, or apart from their
context. Plato had the ideal of an education which should equate
individual realization and social coherency and stability. His
situation forced his ideal into the notion of a society organized in
stratified classes, losing the individual in the class. The eighteenth
century educational philosophy was highly individualistic in form, but
this form was inspired by a noble and generous social ideal: that of a
society organized to include humanity, and providing for the indefinite
perfectibility of mankind. The idealistic philosophy of Germany in the
early nineteenth century endeavored again to equate the ideals of a free
and complete development of cultured personality with social discipline
and political subordination. It made the national state an intermediary
between the realization of private personality on one side and of
humanity on the other. Consequently, it is equally possible to state
its animating principle with equal truth either in the classic terms of
"harmonious development of all the powers of personality" or in the more
recent terminology of "social efficiency." All this reënforces the
statement which opens this chapter: The conception of education as a
social process and function has no definite meaning until we define the
kind of society we have in mind.
These considerations pave the way for our second conclusion.
One of the fundamental problems of education in and for a democratic
society is set by the conflict of a nationalistic and a wider social
aim. The earlier cosmopolitan and "humanitarian" conception suffered
both from vagueness and from lack of definite organs of execution and
agencies of administration. In Europe, in the Continental states
particularly, the new idea of the importance of education for human
welfare and progress was captured by national interests and harnessed to
do a work whose social aim was definitely narrow and exclusive. The
social aim of education and its national aim were identified, and the
result was a marked obscuring of the meaning of a social aim.
This confusion corresponds to the existing situation of human
intercourse. On the one hand, science, commerce, and art transcend
national boundaries. They are largely international in quality and
method. They involve interdependencies and coöperation among the
peoples inhabiting different countries. At the same time, the idea of
national sovereignty has never been as accentuated in politics as it is
at the present time. Each nation lives in a state of suppressed
hostility and incipient war with its neighbors. Each is supposed to be
the supreme judge of its own interests, and it is assumed as matter of
course that each has interests which are exclusively its own. To
question this is to question the very idea of national sovereignty which
is assumed to be basic to political practice and political science.
This contradiction (for it is nothing less) between the wider sphere of
associated and mutually helpful social life and the narrower sphere of
exclusive and hence potentially hostile pursuits and purposes, exacts of
educational theory a clearer conception of the meaning of "social" as a
function and test of education than has yet been attained.
Is it possible for an educational system to be conducted by a national
state and yet the full social ends of the educative process not be
restricted, constrained, and corrupted? Internally, the question has to
face the tendencies, due to present economic conditions, which split
society into classes some of which are made merely tools for the higher
culture of others. Externally, the question is concerned with the
reconciliation of national loyalty, of patriotism, with superior
devotion to the things which unite men in common ends, irrespective of
national political boundaries. Neither phase of the problem can be
worked out by merely negative means. It is not enough to see to it that
education is not actively used as an instrument to make easier the
exploitation of one class by another. School facilities must be secured
of such amplitude and efficiency as will in fact and not simply in name
discount the effects of economic inequalities, and secure to all the
wards of the nation equality of equipment for their future careers.
Accomplishment of this end demands not only adequate administrative
provision of school facilities, and such supplementation of family
resources as will enable youth to take advantage of them, but also such
modification of traditional ideals of culture, traditional subjects of
study and traditional methods of teaching and discipline as will retain
all the youth under educational influences until they are equipped to be
masters of their own economic and social careers. The ideal may seem
remote of execution, but the democratic ideal of education is a farcical
yet tragic delusion except as the ideal more and more dominates our
public system of education.
The same principle has application on the side of the considerations
which concern the relations of one nation to another. It is not enough
to teach the horrors of war and to avoid everything which would
stimulate international jealousy and animosity. The emphasis must be
put upon whatever binds people together in coöperative human pursuits
and results, apart from geographical limitations. The secondary and
provisional character of national sovereignty in respect to the fuller,
freer, and more fruitful association and intercourse of all human beings
with one another must be instilled as a working disposition of mind. If
these applications seem to be remote from a consideration of the
philosophy of education, the impression shows that the meaning of the
idea of education previously developed has not been adequately grasped.
This conclusion is bound up with the very idea of education as a freeing
of individual capacity in a progressive growth directed to social aims.
Otherwise a democratic criterion of education can only be inconsistently
applied.
Summary.
—Since education is a social process, and there are many kinds of
societies, a criterion for educational criticism and construction
implies a particular social ideal. The two points selected by which to
measure the worth of a form of social life are the extent in which the
interests of a group are shared by all its members, and the fullness and
freedom with which it interacts with other groups. An undesirable
society, in other words, is one which internally and externally sets up
barriers to free intercourse and communication of experience. A society
which makes provision for participation in its good of all its members
on equal terms and which secures flexible readjustment of its
institutions through interaction of the different forms of associated
life is in so far democratic. Such a society must have a type of
education which gives individuals a personal interest in social
relationships and control, and the habits of mind which secure social
changes without introducing disorder.
Three typical historic philosophies of education were considered from
this point of view. The Platonic was found to have an ideal formally
quite similar to that stated, but which was compromised in its working
out by making a class rather than an individual the social unit. The
so-called individualism of the eighteenth-century enlightenment was
found to involve the notion of a society as broad as humanity, of whose
progress the individual was to be the organ. But it lacked any agency
for securing the development of its ideal as was evidenced in its
falling back upon Nature. The institutional idealistic philosophies of
the nineteenth century supplied this lack by making the national state
the agency, but in so doing narrowed the conception of the social aim to
those who were members of the same political unit, and reintroduced the
idea of the subordination of the individual to the institution.
Footnotes
[[5]]
There is a much neglected strain in Rousseau tending intellectually in
this direction. He opposed the existing state of affairs on the ground
that it formed neither the citizen nor the man. Under existing
conditions, he preferred to try for the latter rather than for the former.
But there are many sayings of his which point to the formation of the
citizen as ideally the higher, and which indicate that his own endeavor,
as embodied in the Emile, was simply the best makeshift the corruption of
the times permitted him to sketch.