V
The Jesuits took seriously Leibniz' advice to send
more useful objects and
practical information to
Europe from China. They also continued
throughout
the eighteenth century, even after the suppression of
the
Society in 1773, to publish detailed information
on Chinese life ranging
from the history of the Jews
in China to brief essays on Chinese games. The
Lettres
édifiantes et curieuses,
an intentional popularization,
were issued in printed form beginning in
1702, and
were later compiled and reissued in twenty-six volumes
at
Paris between 1780 and 1783. J. B. Du Halde, one
of the editors of the
Lettres édifiantes, published in
four volumes his encyclopedic Description de la
Chine
... (Paris, 1735) which was translated into English
and
Dutch in the following year. In following the encyclo-
pedic tradition which they helped to inaugurate,
the
Jesuits published at intervals from 1777 to 1814 what
were called
Mémoires concernant les Chinois
(Paris).
Unlike their earlier publications, the Jesuits, who were
now
generally in disrepute, here issued in sixteen vol-
umes, with but few editorial coomments, a wide vari-
ety of translations of Chinese materials. Contem-
poraneously, Father Mauriac de
Mailla published in
1778 a translation in twelve volumes of the
Tung-chien,
kang-mu (“The Outline and
Details of the Compre-
hensive
Mirror”), a twelfth-century version of Chinese
history prepared
under the direction of the philosopher
Chu Hsi.
What most impressed the Jesuits and Leibniz about
China, was its superiority
to Europe in the establish-
ment and
maintenance of a rational social order.
Leibniz fancied from what he read
that the K'ang-hsi
emperor was a model ruler who governed his subjects
firmly but with great respect for law and the advice
of his counsellors. So
great was Leibniz' admiration
for the government, social stability, and
moral system
of the Chinese that he confessed:
... we need missionaries from the Chinese who might teach
us the use
and practice of natural religion, just as we have
sent them
teachers of revealed theology
(trans. in Lach,
Novissima Sinica, p. 75).
To Leibniz and the Jesuits, the morality of the
Chinese was inseparable from
government. The
Chinese, it was alleged, have no concern with abstract
questions of morality but are interested only in apply-
ing to daily life the teachings of Confucius
regarding
the duties of men. The morality of the Chinese is seen
to be
a set of prescriptions designed to procure and
assure individual, familial,
and social happiness. The
successful organization of the Chinese monarchy,
as
opposed to the European states, is based on the fact
that the
emperor applies and adapts to the adminis-
tration of the state the principles which obtain in
individual
and family life. Political means are used in
China to achieve a more
perfect morality. The end
of life, society, and government in China is
happiness,
here and now. Abstract religious virtue, with its invisi-
ble and other worldly rewards, is of no
interest to the
Chinese. China flourishes as a great and virtuous em-
pire without the aid of revealed religion.
Among the earliest of the philosophical popularizers
to propagate to the
learned public the Sinophilism of
the Jesuits was Christian Wolff, the
follower of Leibniz.
In a lecture delivered at the University of Halle
in
1721 before the combined faculty and student body,
Wolff proclaimed
the excellence of Chinese moral
philosophy and its correspondence with his
own teach-
ings regarding the efficacy of
human reason in meeting
the problems of daily life. Duty and virtue, the
differ-
ence between good and evil, and
the imperative to
right action may be learned from nature as well as
revelation, according to both the Chinese and Wolff.
While Wolff contends
that no conflict exists between
this doctrine of lay morality and Christian teachings,
his Pietistic colleagues at the university remained un-
convinced. In their determination to end
what they
thought of as Wolff's heretical teachings, the Pietists
prevailed in 1723 upon King Frederick William I of
Prussia to banish Wolff
from his territories.
From the sanctuary of the University of Marburg
Wolff continued thereafter
to write about and teach
his “practical philosophy.”
Others continued to write
polemical tracts about Wolff and his
interpretations
of Confucian morality and Chinese statecraft. In 1730
at Marburg Wolff delivered a lengthy lecture on China
as the outstanding
working example of an enlightened
government. His views of the
“Real Happiness of a
People under a Philosophical
King” did not go un-
noticed by
Voltaire and the young Frederick whom
he was tutoring at Rheinsberg. Within
German univer-
sity circles the moral
philosophy and Sinophilism of
Wolff continued to be a subject for learned
debate until
the last generation of the eighteenth century. Wolff's
major pronouncements on Chinese morality and gov-
ernment were greeted with great cordiality by the
Jesuits. In
the Description of Du Halde, issued five years
after
Wolff's lecture at Marburg, emphasis continued
to be placed upon the
natural morality, rational reli-
gion, and
enlightened statecraft of the Chinese.
The first systematic treatise on the science of state-
craft published in Europe was Montesquieu's L'esprit
des lois (The Spirit of
the Laws, 1748). For his informa-
tion on China Montesquieu used the merchant accounts
as well as the
adulatory statements of the Jesuits, but
preferred the merchants as the
less biased observers.
The merchants, as we have seen, were as
unanimous
in their condemnation of the treachery, deceit, and
dishonesty of the Chinese as the Jesuits were in their
praise of China's
natural morality and good govern-
ment. In
response to the conflict in his sources, and
in harmony with the thesis of
his book, Montesquieu
concluded that a wide gulf separates theory from
prac-
tice in the governing of China. Peace
and tranquillity
are assured by patriarchal repression and by the do-
minion of fear. An attack upon a magistrate
becomes
an attack upon the entire system, hence dissent and
liberty
are nonexistent and reform of evil impossible.
As long as the elements are
cooperative, the people
industrious, and the state not too repressive, life
in
China is satisfactory. But nature is not often benign
and so
disruptions occur. And, since reform of the state
is not possible, the
individual Chinese make out as best
they can by resorting to artifice. The
state, handcuffed
by its own system, tolerates deception while
eschewing
reform. China, because it is governed by the rod, is
classified as a despotism in which honor and virtue are
little more than
theoretical objectives. Nonetheless, by
the attention he gave to China,
Montesquieu recog-
nized that study of its laws and institutions is necessary
to
any objective examination of the principles of gov-
ernment and similar questions of universal import.
Rousseau, in his Discourse on Political Economy
(first
printed in the Encyclopédie in 1755)
likewise experi-
enced the need to reckon
with China in propounding
his generalizations. The emperor of China he sees
as
being exemplary in unswervingly following the dictates
of the
“general will” in resolving disputes between the
officials and the people. Rousseau approvingly noted
that it is
“the constant maxim of the prince to decide
against his
officers” without delay or investigation, and
concludes that
since the “public outcry does not arise
without
cause” the Chinese emperor finds “seldom any
injustice to be repaired.” He also praised the fiscal
system of
China “where taxes are greater and yet better
paid than in any
other part of the world.” The reason
for this, in Rousseau's
estimation, is that food grains
are free of taxes, and the heavy duties
levied on other
commodities are paid by the ultimate consumer, or by
those who can afford to pay.
Voltaire in his historical works, especially in the
Essai sur les moeurs et l'esprit des nations
(1756),
measured China's civilization against the achievements
of
other peoples. China occupies the place of honor
in his Essai and is the first civilization he considers.
The Chinese are
especially successful, in Voltaire's
eyes, in using government to protect
civilization. The
emperors of China, comparable to philosopher-kings,
for centuries maintained a stable, tolerant, and wise
regime. Their benign,
patriarchal rule, reinforced and
aided by a corps of dedicated mandarins,
served the
people well. Society, following the Confucian princi-
ples, was built on respect for the
Golden Rule, mutual
toleration, and public service. In upholding the Confu-
cian ideals, the Chinese produced
throughout history
an intelligent, rational, and deistic ruling class
which
set an example to the rest of society by cultivating
virtue,
refined manners, and an elevated style of life.
But the Chinese system, for
all of its moral and political
virtue, could do nothing to encourage the
expansion
of the arts and sciences. Superstition, ancestor worship,
and the character system of the language were persist-
ent deterrents to advancement. The consequence
was
that China did not develop the arts and sciences as
it might have
done. That China's ancient civilization
was overtaken by the European in
the mid-seventeenth
century is best documented by the fact that
“even”
the Jesuits were able to teach the mandarins
something
from their first arrival on the Chinese scene.
If Voltaire's Sinophilism was qualified, a number of
political theorists of
the mid-eighteenth century were
convinced that Europe had more to learn
from China
than it had to teach. In Germany, a leading cameralist
writer of the day, J. H. G. Justi published in Berlin
in 1762
Vergleichungen der europäischen mit den
asiatischen und andern vermeintlich barbarischen
Regierungen.
In this comparative work, as well as in
several of his other writings on
political economy, Justi
concentrates on China as the foreign state most
worthy
of study. He is particularly attracted by China as an
example
of enlightened monarchy in which the un-
limited authority of the ruler is effectually combined
with
moderation in its exercise. Moral restraint in the
monarch is inculcated in
China by careful education
of the prince in humility, industry, respect for
human
life, reverence for learning, and concern for agricul-
ture, the main occupation of the people. Like
Leibniz,
he believed that the Chinese emperor is constrained
to virtue
by his desire to receive the favorable judg-
ment of history. While subjects have the duty to re-
monstrate with the ruler, he sees in China no formal
constitutional restrictions on the emperor. Systematic
training in civil
morality is taught to the people by
the mandarins, who are themselves
selected, rated, and
promoted by a civil service institution. No
hereditary
nobility exists in China, and elevation to high rank
comes
only through excellent performance in public
service. The censorate, which
acts as the eyes and ears
of the emperor, is the surveillance institution
that
guarantees integrity and efficiency at all levels of gov-
ernment. Administration by boards rather
than by
individuals alone also helps to check license and des-
potism among officials. Most impressive of
all is the
fact that the Chinese system is internally so well bal-
anced and its administrative machinery so
wisely con-
structed that it works automatically to insure the gen-
eral welfare. In China, Justi clearly thought he had
found a
working example of the kind of enlightened
despotism that he and others
were advocating for the
German states.
In France the ideal of an enlightened and rational
absolutism was most fully
articulated by the Physio-
crats. The
Physiocrats were especially critical of state
economic policies which
overstress commerce and
neglect agriculture. In China they saw a
government
vitally concerned with agriculture, as was symbolized
dramatically by the annual spring rites at which the
emperor, or his
deputy, turned the first furrow. The
most characteristic of the
Physiocratic writings which
elevated China to a model for Europe was
François
Quesnay's Le despotisme de la
Chine (Paris, 1767).
Quesnay sees the government of China as one
in which
the ruler through legal despotism enforces the natural
economic laws. Authority is rightly invested in an
emperor who is
impartial, tolerant, and constantly
careful to protect the public welfare.
Since China is
an agricultural nation, the ruler correctly pays special
attention to problems relating to the land and the
cultivator.
He does not lay arbitrary taxes, but follows
the Natural Law by requiring
as payment “a portion
of the annual produce of the
soil” (Maverick, p. 290).
He does not tolerate monopolies, but
does his best to
encourage free and natural competition in all
economic
enterprises. He demands regular accountings of public
funds
and swiftly punishes malversations. The per-
petuity of China's government is attributed to the
stable natural
order enforced by the ruler. China's
greatest problem is overcrowding of
the land with the
result that too many of its people live in poverty
or
slavery.