Dictionary of the History of Ideas Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas |
VI. |
V. |
VI. |
I. |
VI. |
V. |
III. |
III. |
VI. |
VI. |
V. |
V. |
III. |
VII. |
VI. |
VI. |
III. |
III. |
II. |
I. |
I. |
I. |
V. |
VII. |
VI. |
V. |
III. |
III. |
III. |
II. |
I. |
I. |
I. |
VI. |
VII. |
III. |
VII. |
VII. |
I. SUBSTANTIVE THEORIES
|
VII. |
V. |
VI. |
VI. |
VI. |
VI. |
VI. |
VII. |
III. |
IV. |
VI. |
VI. |
VI. |
V. |
V. |
V. |
III. |
III. |
VII. |
III. |
I. |
V. |
V. |
VII. |
VI. |
I. |
I. |
I. |
I. |
VI. |
III. |
IV. |
III. |
IV. |
IV. |
IV. |
VI. |
VI. |
VI. |
V. |
III. |
VI. |
Dictionary of the History of Ideas | ||
I. SUBSTANTIVE THEORIES
What, if anything, underlies the course of history
as a whole? What are the
fundamental or real deter-
minants of
historical change? Can any one factor be
picked out as being of preeminent
importance? Is it
possible to formulate causal laws that hold universally
throughout the domain of historical experience? What
is the
role of human thought and decision in history,
and how far is it
justifiable to impute moral respon-
sibility for their actions to individual historical figures?
Is it
legitimate to regard accident or chance as playing
a significant part in
deciding the direction taken by
historical events? Is historical
determinism true, and
if so what are its implications? These constitute
some
of the questions that have been asked by theorists
preoccupied by
the problem of giving an account of
causality as it manifests itself within
the field of the
human past. Not only have they generated a host of
diverse and often conflicting answers; they have also
been raised at
different levels of enquiry and with
distinguishable considerations in
mind.
Theological and Metaphysical Conceptions.
It is not,
for instance, the case that the causal agencies
regarded
as determining the sequence of occurrences have al-
ways been conceived to be empirical factors lying
within the historical process. On the contrary, it has
sometimes been
assumed that the clue to all that hap-
pens must
ultimately be located in something that lies
outside that process, such as
the will of a divine or
transcendent being. One potent source of
speculation
has been the belief that the pattern of historical events
represents the unfolding of some overall purpose or
design, views of this
sort originating in religious notions
of the universe and of man's place
within it. Thus, early
in the Christian era, certain of the Church fathers
were
already reacting against Greco-Roman views that
pictured history
in terms of recurrent cycles, seeking
to substitute a conception of linear
movement wherein
the intentions of a sovereign providential power were
clearly discoverable; while by the fifth century Saint
Augustine had given
articulate philosophical expression
to a directional view which presupposed
a providential
order and which was to prove immensely influential.
Augustine's ideas admittedly diverged widely from the
cruder hypotheses of
his predecessors; moreover, he
was notably reticent about the possibility
of interpret-
ing the details of
terrestrial history in a providential
manner, implying for the most part
that such things
fell outside the range of human cognizance and con-
cern. The same cannot, however, be said of
some later
writers who looked back to Augustine for inspiration,
and
least of all of the seventeenth-century French
historian, J. B. Bossuet.
Bossuet's Discours sur l'histoire
universelle
(1681) was indeed remarkable for the con-
fidence displayed by its author in his capacity for
penetrating the
workings of the divine intelligence
insofar as these impinged upon the
affairs of men. It
was not merely that he took pleasure in offering exam-
ples of the retribution visited by God upon
erring
nations and individuals; he further professed to know
had been “contrived by a higher wisdom, that is to
say, in the everlasting mind who has all the world's
causes and all the effects contained in one single order.”
The modern development of historical enquiry as
a firmly established
discipline in its own right has
been—not
unnaturally—accompanied by a marked
decline in the tendency to
try to explain the general
course of history by reference to a governing
agency
external to it. It is true that some latter-day theologians,
for example, Reinhold Niebuhr, have spoken as if cer-
tain forms of providential interpretation remained fea-
sible: but the proposals put forward have
usually been
so tentative and heavily qualified, so imbued with a
desire not to trespass upon areas occupied by profes-
sional or “technical” historians,
that to treat them as
strictly comparable with the ambitious programs
of
earlier periods would be a mistake. Nevertheless, the
view that the
totality of historical events can and
should be understood as composing an
intelligible tele-
ological sequence has
been a persistent one in human
thinking, and in the eighteenth and
nineteenth cen-
turies this found expression
in systems in which the
purposive element stressed by previous
theological
writers was, so to speak, absorbed within the historical
process itself. Thus various attempts were made to
portray history as
moving in a determinate and mean-
ingful
direction, but without thereby positing a tran-
scendent entity which could be regarded as ultimately
responsible for the direction it took; the providential
principle was
regarded as being immanent in world
history rather than as deriving from an
extraneous
source.
Some such thought underlies the theories of history
propounded by Vico,
Kant, and Hegel. Despite their
considerable differences on other counts,
these philos-
ophers at least shared the
common assumption or
methodological postulate that what happens in the
historical sphere possesses an inner “logic” which
can
be regarded as being intrinsic to the course of events.
By this
they did not mean that the actual participants
in the process were always
aware of the long-term
significance of their actions: on the contrary,
they
implied that the historical purposes served by particu-
lar agents were obscure or even unknown to the
agents
themselves; it was only in retrospect—and from a
vantage point that transcended the contingencies of
immediate occasion and
circumstance—that the deeds
of individuals could be seen as
contributing towards
the realization of a state of affairs which was in
some
sense implicit from the beginning as a final goal or
end. At the
same time, they did not wish to be under-
stood as recommending a kind of applied theology.
When Vico, for
instance, spoke of there being an “ideal
eternal history... whose course is run in time by the
histories
of all nations” (Scienza nuova,
§114), he ex-
pressly repudiated the
suggestion that he was postulat-
ing a
divine “potter who molds things outside himself.”
It
was man who made his own history; he did so,
however, in a fashion such
that each stage of social
development could be interpreted as having a part
to
play in a sequence that, taken as a whole, displayed
a necessary
teleological structure. Likewise, Kant was
insistent upon the possibility
of conceiving history in
a way that portrayed the conflicts and
vicissitudes to
which men are subject by virtue of their own
activities
as representing the means whereby the human species
progressively realized the capacities originally im-
planted in it by nature and thus moved towards the
fulfilment of
its earthly destiny. The case of Hegel is
more complicated, since his
conception of history was
impregnated with conceptions deriving from a
com-
prehensive metaphysical system
that encompassed
every aspect of human experience; yet here, too, a
similar theme may be discerned. For history, along
with everything else,
exemplified the unfolding of a
rational principle or
“Idea” that was destined to realize
itself in time.
Hegel admittedly spoke of the operations
of a “World
Spirit” (Weltgeist) in history, but he
does
not seem to have envisaged this as an independent
agency; rather,
it expressed itself directly in the activi-
ties of historical individuals and was nothing apart from
these. So
understood, the historical process moved
inexorably forward, one phase
giving way to another
in a dialectical progression that culminated in a
form
of social life which—as the embodiment of
freedom—
constituted its ultimate objective, being referred to
by
Hegel as “the final cause of the world at large.”
Hegel himself sometimes gave the impression that
his interpretation of
history could be regarded as a
“hypothesis” that both
accounted for and was grounded
upon the empirical data at his disposal. And
a major
attraction, indeed, of teological theories of the type
to
which his may be said to belong has been the feeling
that, unlike
explicitly theological conceptions, they do
not in the end require for
their support anything other
than the attested facts of historical
experience. Such
a feeling is understandable. For what, from one point
of view, the historical teleologist can be considered
to be doing is making
a claim to the effect that a
certain trend or tendency has manifested
itself in
human affairs; and such a claim, it would seem, is one
fully
capable of being confirmed or disproved by expe-
rience alone. It is, however, one thing to assert that
events
have, as a matter of fact, exhibited a particular
tendency or direction; it
is another to say that it was
necessary that they should have taken the
course that
they did: and it is another again to seek to confirm this
they have issued or to which they eventually led. To
argue that certain things had to happen if something
else was to happen is not in itself to explain why the
earlier events in the series occurred as they did; the
most that would be shown is that the occurrence of
the prior events was a necessary condition of the oc-
currence of the sequel. The situation would, of course,
be different if, on independent grounds, it could be
demonstrated that the end-product of history was in
some manner intended or preordained from the start
and, moreover, that there was only one route by which
such a consummation could be attained. But it remains
hard to see how such an additional assumption could
be established, or even assigned a clear meaning, in
the absence of anything over and above the facts of
man's past as determined by ordinary historical inves-
tigation. For this reason, among others, a number of
empirically-minded theorists, such as Saint-Simon and
Comte, were led to look elsewhere in their search for
an explanatory key with which to unlock the secrets
of historical evolution and change.
The Quest for Causal Laws.
One factor which, from
the Enlightenment onwards, exercised a
pervasive in-
fluence upon the development of
historical speculation
was the progress of the natural sciences. The dis-
coveries of men like Galileo, Kepler, and
Newton had
apparently opened the way to unlimited advance in
the
exploration of nature, showing how ranges of phys-
ical phenomena, often of the most diverse kinds, could
be
systematically accommodated and unified within
schemes of vast explanatory
and predictive power. It
was, furthermore, a feature of the theories and
laws
propounded that they had been evolved within the
setting of a
mechanistic rather than a teleological
conception of the universe: enquiry
was guided by the
aim of determining the detectable conditions under
which phenomena occurred, the uniformities of se-
quence which they exhibited in precisely specifiable
circumstances, rather than by considerations involving
the supposition that
they were activated by purposive
principles mysteriously embedded in the
structure of
the cosmos. It is not surprising that the possibility of
applying similar approaches and techniques to the
study of psychological
and social phenomena should
have occurred to thinkers to whom it appeared
un-
reasonable and obscurantist to
assume the existence of
an absolute gulf separating the realm of nature
from
the realm of mind. Why should the thought and be-
havior of human beings not be subject to universal and
necessary regularities comparable to those that gov-
erned physical reality? At the individual level this
attitude
was to find expression in such “materialist”
works as
Holbach's Système de la nature (1770) and
La Mettrie's L'Homme machine (1748),
as well as in
the “associationist” psychological
doctrines of eigh-
teenth- and
nineteenth-century British empiricism. Its
most spectacular and influential
manifestations, how-
ever, took place within the
province of social theory:
here a determined effort was made to lay the
founda-
tions of a historical science
which would not only rival
the natural sciences in richness and scope but
would
also provide a firm theoretical base from which to
conduct
large-scale projects of social reorganization
and reform. The practical
advantages that would ac-
crue from a proper
understanding of the fundamental
determinants of history were seldom far
from the minds
of those who undertook to achieve it.
If causal laws were operative within history, what
form did they take and
how were they to be discov-
ered? As a number
of recent critics have been at pains
to point out, the enthusiastic
advocacy of a scientific
approach to human affairs was not always matched
by
a corresponding grasp of the actual nature of scientific
method and
inference. Thus some theorists were apt
to rely upon a rather naive mode of
induction by
simple enumeration in arriving at their conclusions;
one
consequence of this was a proneness to overlook
or leave out of account
possible counter-examples to
the principles or generalizations they
supposed them-
selves to have established.
Again, it is arguable that
the interpretations they put upon certain
crucial con-
cepts were on occasions open to
objection. Karl Pop-
per, for instance, has
maintained that the term “law”
was not infrequently
used incorrectly, being misappro-
priated to apply to what were in fact no more than
particular trends
or long-term processes; insofar as
these were regarded as possessing some
sort of inherent
necessity, it was perhaps partly due to the survival
of
teleological preconceptions which, though openly re-
pudiated, nonetheless continued to exert a covert in-
fluence. Yet another persistent feature of
scientifically-
inspired
theories of history was the restriction they
imposed upon the range of
conditions considered to
be basically or “decisively”
relevant: it was assumed
that the fundamental laws of historical
development
should be formulable in a manner that gave priority
to
factors of some specific type—race, environment,
and the growth
of knowledge or technology being
among those variously accorded this
privileged status.
As a result many of the theories in question were
monistic in character, presupposing a sharp contrast
between, on the one
hand, merely superficial or “ap-
parent” causative agencies and, on the other, deep-
lying forces to whose operation the
general shape and
direction taken by significant social phenomena must
in the last analysis be ascribed. Yet here, once more,
it was often far
from clear what justification, empirical
tions and limitations of the kind referred to. Some of
these tendencies, and their accompanying difficulties,
are illustrated in the works of two nineteenth-century
thinkers whose writings made a profound impact upon
their age: H. T. Buckle and Karl Marx.
Buckle had been impressed by his reading of Auguste
Comte and J. S. Mill,
themselves both wedded to the
conception of a social science, and he
regarded it as
a scandal that so little had previously been done
“to-
wards discovering the
principles which govern the
character and destiny of nations.”
In particular, he
heaped ridicule upon doctrines—such as those
ascrib-
ing to men a power of undetermined
free choice—
which in his view had hindered the creation of
a
genuinely scientific interpretation of history. Against
obfuscatory
and “metaphysical” dogmas of this kind
he affirmed
the “undeviating regularity” with which
human actions
followed upon antecedent circum-
stances,
and he set out to provide a detailed account
of the fashion in which what
he called “three vast
agents”—climate,
food, and soil—combined to deter-
mine the original character and evolution of different
peoples and
cultures. Buckle's erudition was consid-
erable and his deployment of it to substantiate his
claims was not
devoid of value, leading other historians
to take seriously matters that
had not received the
attention they deserved. Yet what he said can
hardly
be considered to have fulfilled his own ambitious aspi-
rations. His generalizations were
conspicuously lacking
in precision, and his denial that such factors as
govern-
ment and religion could properly
be regarded as
“prime movers of human affairs”
functioned more as
a prejudice than as an argued thesis. Moreover,
having
proved to his satisfaction that a particular condition
was
necessary to the production of some social out-
come, he was liable to pass without further ado to the
conclusion
that it was sufficient as well. Thus his con-
duct of the enterprise he had undertaken seemed often
to be vitiated
by logical confusions in addition to the
methodological inadequacies it
displayed.
Marx's conception of history was subtler, and in
general has proved to be
far more fertile in its conse-
quences for
historical writing and research. Roughly
speaking, it involved the
contention that the final
determinant of historical movement was to be
found,
not in the ideas men entertained, but in their material
activities and methods of production; it was the ma-
nipulative interaction between man and his environ-
ment—the ways in which men
worked upon it in order
to create their means of subsistence and to satisfy
their
developing needs and wants—that was responsible for
the course taken by human affairs, necessitating the
form assumed by
phenomena in other departments of
social life and experience. Marx and his
followers were
thereby led to distinguish between the economic
“base” of society (consisting in the productive
forces
together with the class alignments these forces gave
rise to)
and the ideological “superstructure” (compris-
ing religion, ethics, political
institutions, systems of
law, and so forth), the latter being essentially
the
product of the former. History could thus be seen as
owing its
momentum to changes that took place in
human productive techniques and to
corresponding
movements and conflicts within the social structure:
as
Marx and Engels wrote in their German Ideology
(1845-46), “men, developing their material production
and their
material intercourse, alter, along with this
their real existence, their
thinking and the products
of their thinking” (p. 38). Such a
theory possessed a
challenging originality and economy; it appeared
both
to illuminate hitherto uncharted ranges of historical
phenomena
and also to set in a new light, at times
even to undermine, such
traditional modes of explana-
tion as those
that emphasized individual plans and
projects and the beliefs or ideals
that inspired them.
Yet, despite the insights it undoubtedly embodied,
the
very comprehensiveness and neatness of the Marxian
interpretation
was felt by some to mask a variety of
problems concerning its validity and
its application in
practice to the material it was designed to
explain.
How far, for example, was it possible to describe or
identify
the factors assigned to the economic base or
“foundation” without introducing considerations of a
political or juristic nature? What exactly were the
grounds for asserting
that ethical or political doctrines
were essentially expressions of the
interests of econom-
ically determined
classes, and how was such an hy-
pothesis to
be empirically tested? Or again, was it
legitimate to treat the role of
individual personalities
in history as cavalierly as Engels, in particular,
some-
times implied? More generally, could
it not be argued
that the progressivist optimism, implicit in the
Marxian
notion of history as moving inexorably forward towards
the
creation of social forms that would render possible
the complete
realization of human potentialities, owed
more to the postulates of the
Idealist metaphysic Marx
had absorbed in his youth than to any entailed by
a
strictly scientific methodology? It was one thing (such
critics
protested) to stress the importance of economic
factors and to show how
these might exert an unsus-
pected but
nonetheless crucial influence upon historical
change; it was surely quite
another to suggest that,
once their significance had been appreciated, the
entire
historical process would present itself as conforming
to a
necessary pattern in such a way that future phases
of its development could
be unerringly predicted.
Pluralistic and Antinomian Views.
Ideas like those
of Buckle and Marx brought to the fore issues that
have
not always been clearly distinguished. Thus the ques-
to some unitary principle (whether teleological or
causal in character) has sometimes been identified with
the question of whether history can be said to form
an intelligible field of study, susceptible to rational
understanding and elucidation. The twentieth-century
historian Arnold Toynbee has, for example, suggested
that in the absence of such a principle, history would
amount to no more than a “chaotic, fortuitous, dis-
orderly flux”; while others have spoken as if the sole
alternative to regarding historical phenomena as ulti-
mately determined by some specific set of material or
social forces was to relegate them to the sphere of the
merely random and contingent. Alleged dilemmas of
this kind may be challenged, however, on the grounds
both that they exploit ambiguities inherent in such
notions as intelligibility and contingency and that at
the same time they presuppose a too restricted model
of acceptable explanation. It can be maintained, for
instance, that a pluralistic conception of historical
causation—one, that is, which ascribes causal efficacy
to a variety of independent factors without according
paramount status to those of any single type—is in no
way incompatible with the belief that historical events
and developments can be rendered intelligible in a
perfectly straightforward sense; it has, indeed, been
argued that such a conception accurately reflects the
practice of the majority of working historians, few of
whom would admit that they were thereby committed
to the view that their subject matter was in some
fashion radically incoherent or intractable. Nor, like-
wise, need a historian think that history is the product
of arbitrary caprice, or even that it is essentially (in
Carlyle's famous phrase) “the biography of great men,”
if he subscribes to the opinion that the characters and
decisions of individual figures often play a central and
irreducible role in determining what occurs. In this
connection it is interesting to observe that the Marxian
theorist G. V. Plekhanov (1857-1918), himself an
avowed adherent to the “monist view of history” and
insistent upon the stringent limits that social conditions
and “general causes” imposed upon the capacity of
individuals to affect the course of events, was none-
theless prepared to allow that personal disposition and
talent, as expressed in the activities of individuals,
could make a real difference to what happened in
certain historical contexts. Any theory (he held) which
tried wholly to dispense with a consideration of indi-
vidual factors would assume an implausible “fatalistic”
appearance, just as one that by contrast attributed
everything to these would end, absurdly, by depicting
history as an inconsequential and wholly fortuitous
series of happenings.
A further source of difficulty and confusion has been
the tendency to
conflate issues of the kind discussed
with others relating to the place of freedom in history
and to
the general status of determinism. As Buckle
correctly noted, a powerful
motive for resisting deter-
ministic or
scientifically orientated conceptions of his-
torical development has been the conviction that their
acceptance is inconsistent with a belief in human free
will and
responsibility. One characteristic reaction to
such theories has
accordingly taken the form of em-
phasizing
the decisive contributions made by out-
standing individuals and of arguing that if, for example,
Napoleon
or Lenin had not been born, European his-
tory
might have followed a markedly different course.
But the claim that the
deeds of particular personalities
have often had profound long-term effects
does not by
itself entail that the historical process cannot be re-
garded as constituting a causally determined
sequence.
All that the determinist postulates (it may be objected)
is
that, given any historical event, an explanation of
the occurrence of that
event could in principle be
provided in terms of causally sufficient
conditions. And
this in no sense contradicts the contention that
“great
men” or “world-historical
individuals” sometimes ex-
ercise a
decisive influence upon what happens; what
it states is that, if and when
they do, their choices and
actions must themselves always be susceptible to
a
complete causal explanation.
Somewhat similar considerations apply to the claim
that the obtrusion of
accidental or chance happenings
into history represents a refutation of
deterministic
assumptions. It is, of course, quite true that
historians
are apt to employ the notions of chance
or accident
in the course of unfolding their
narratives and explana-
tions: this was a
feature strongly underlined by the
British historian J. B. Bury. However,
as Bury himself
pointed out in a well-known essay entitled
“Cleopatra's
Nose,” it is a mistake to conclude from
that that the
use of such concepts presupposes “the intrusion of
a
lawless element” into history. It would appear rather
that, when a historian refers to something as having
happened by chance, he
implies that its explanation
lies—in a manner admittedly not
easy to characterize
with precision—off the main track of his
enquiry or
concern. An event that is described as fortuitous or
accidental in the context of one set of interests may
take on a different
aspect when it is surveyed from
another standpoint, being seen there as
intrinsically
related to the historian's principal theme or subject:
in neither case, though, need the suggestion that it has
no causal
explanation be present. Bury himself, echoing
the account provided by A.
Cournot in his Considéra-
tions sur la marche des idées
et des événements dans
les temps modernes
(1872), referred to chance as in-
volving the
“valuable collision of two or more inde-
pendent chains of causes.” As a definition this may
not
be impeccable, but it at least avoids the pitfall of
historian is irrevocably committed to some form of
indeterminism.
Dictionary of the History of Ideas | ||