University of Virginia Library

Search this document 
Dictionary of the History of Ideas

Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas
  
  
expand section 
  
expand section 
  
  

expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
collapse sectionIII. 
  
collapse section 
  
  
  
  
expand section 
  
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionVII. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionIV. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionVI. 
expand sectionV. 
expand sectionIII. 
expand sectionVI. 

IV. SPECIES

In folklore the animals and plants had clear-cut
natures, including moral characterizations such as we
find in Aesop and in the Oriental and African fables.
The ancients believed that some types regularly meta-
morphose into each other, for example, cuckoo hawk
and hoopoe interchange, and wheat can become darnel.
By this they meant a change of identity, not an ambi-
guity between these types, nor a seasonal change (as
stoat to ermine).

Plato was the first to apply a philosophical technique
to the conception of animal types. According to his
theory of Forms, we identify natural qualities by com-
paring them with ideal qualities which may not appear
exactly in nature but are known directly to the mind.
The animal type is an aggregate of characters which
approximate to ideal Forms. The Forms therefore are
an absolute reference point.

Aristotle inverts this analysis, by taking the animal
type as the exact object of knowledge, while its char-
acters vary in precision. Some characters are essential,
some not (for instance, the eye may be essential, and
an eye must have a color, but its actual color is ines-
sential and imprecise). The animal type, namely its
species, is a unified pattern of essential characters and
functions. It is identical in all members of the species.
The variations between individuals are due to their
material makeup, not to their form.

There have been so many conceptions of species in
modern times that it is perhaps useful to say what
Aristotle's conception is not. It is not a statistical aver-
age, not a population, not an approximation, not an
arbitrarily selected type-specimen. On the other hand,
it is not a form imposed by God. It is a type-pattern
that exists in nature as an objective datum: it is there
to be detected within individuals. It differs from any
one individual as absolutely as the mathematical circle
differs from a drawing of a circle. It is this species-
pattern that Aristotle believes to be eternally repro-
duced in nature, for that is the nearest that sublunary
beings can get to the eternal cyclic movement of the
stars. The fact that it may never be exactly reproduced
does not affect his point, which is that nature tends
to reproduce it.

This conception could easily become a belief in fixed
species, but Aristotle did not consider that point; there
was in fact nothing in his biology that was incompatible
with an evolutionary theory, had the question ever
arisen. He accepted reports of new species resulting
from miscegenation (he quotes dog and fox, dog and
wolf, several fishes and birds). He makes only the pro-
viso that interbreeding is limited to animals that are
alike in species, size, and length of gestation, and that
in any case there could not be indefinite production
of new species, because that would defeat nature's
teleology (meaning that there would be no goals, for
the goal is the reproduction of the parent's form). He
emphasizes that the ladder of nature is continuous, and
that many types overlap the borders of classifications.
Moreover his theory of reproduction is aimed at ex-
plaining how the father's form is transmitted and how
the family likeness may come to be disturbed: the
precise goal is that the animal should “beget another
like itself,” and its specific form is something wider
that is only latent in it. There is a contradiction in
his doctrine here: for he says theoretically that species
is the object of science while individual differences are
due to matter and are unknowable, but in practice he
brings to scientific account many characters that are
below specific level—not only family likeness but ines-
sential attributes such as coloration and voice. Just
occasionally he suggests that individuals differ not only


233

in matter but in form too, since the materials that
individualize them could be stated generally; but he
does not follow this up. (It was followed up by some
medieval scholastics, who thereby removed this diffi-
culty from his theory of individuation.)

Aristotle therefore could have accommodated an
evolutionary theory of species; but he had no need of
it. He had no paleontology, no obsolete species to
consider; similarity of species could be covered by his
theory; and believing that the world had no beginning,
he had no problem of the origins of species. By the
third century A.D. some Stoic and Neo-Platonist theo-
logians had developed the idea that forms and species
are thoughts in the mind of God. It was this idea, rather
than Aristotle's theory, that led later scientists like
Linnaeus to posit the fixity of species.