6.1. 1. Of the Simplicity of Civil Laws in different Governments.
Monarchies do not permit of so great a simplicity of laws as
despotic governments. For in monarchies there must be courts of
judicature; these must give their decisions; the decisions must be
preserved and learned, that we may judge in the same manner to-day as
yesterday, and that the lives and property of the citizens may be as
certain and fixed as the very constitution of the state.
In monarchies, the administration of justice, which decides not only
in whatever belongs to life and property, but likewise to honour,
demands very scrupulous inquiries. The delicacy of the judge increases
in proportion to the increase of his trust, and of the importance of the
interests on which he determines.
We must not, therefore, be surprised to find so many rules,
restrictions, and extensions in the laws of those countries — rules
that multiply the particular cases, and seem to make of reason itself an
art.
The difference of rank, birth, and condition established in
monarchical governments is frequently attended with distinctions in the
nature of property; and the laws relating to the constitution of this
government may augment the number of these distinctions. Hence, among us
goods are divided into real estates, purchases, dowries, paraphernalia,
paternal and maternal inheritances; movables of different kinds; estates
held in fee-simple, or in tail; acquired by descent or conveyance;
allodial, or held by soccage; ground rents; or annuities. Each sort of
goods is subject to particular rules, which must be complied with in the
disposal of them. These things must needs diminish the simplicity of the
laws.
In our governments the fiefs have become hereditary. It was
necessary that the nobility should have a fixed property, that is, the
fief should have a certain consistency, to the end that the proprietor
might be always in a capacity of serving the prince. This must have been
productive of great varieties; for instance, there are countries where
fiefs could not be divided among the brothers; in others, the younger
brothers may be allowed a more generous subsistence.
The monarch who knows each of his provinces may establish different
laws, or tolerate different customs. But as the despotic prince knows
nothing, and can attend to nothing, he must take general measures, and
govern by a rigid and inflexible will, which throughout his whole
dominions produces the same effect; in short, everything bends under his
feet.
In proportion as the decisions of the courts of judicature are
multiplied in monarchies, the law is loaded with decrees that sometimes
contradict one another; either because succeeding judges are of a
different way of thinking, or because the same causes are sometimes
well, and at other times ill, defended; or, in fine, by reason of an
infinite number of abuses, to which all human regulations are liable.
This is a necessary evil, which the legislator redresses from time to
time, as contrary even to the spirit of moderate governments. For when
people are obliged to have recourse to courts of judicature, this should
come from the nature of the constitution, and not from the contradiction
or uncertainty of the law.
In governments where there are necessary distinctions of persons,
there must likewise be privileges. This also diminishes the simplicity,
and creates a thousand exceptions.
One of the privileges least burdensome to society, and especially to
him who confers it, is that of pleading in one court in preference to
another. Here new difficulties arise, when it becomes a question before
which court we shall plead.
Far different is the case of the people under despotic governments.
In those countries I can see nothing that the legislator is able to
decree, or the magistrate to judge. As the lands belong to the prince,
it follows that there are scarcely any civil laws in regard to landed
property. From the right the sovereign has to successions, it follows,
likewise, that there are none relating to inheritances. The monopolies
established by the prince for himself in some countries render all sorts
of commercial laws quite useless. The marriages which they usually
contract with female slaves are the cause that there are scarcely any
civil laws relating to dowries, or to the particular advantage of
married women. From the prodigious multitude of slaves, it follows,
likewise, that there are very few who have any such thing as a will of
their own, and of course are answerable for their conduct before a
judge. Most moral actions that are only in consequence of a father's, a
husband's, or a master's will, are regulated by them, and not by the
magistrates.
I forgot to observe that as what we call honour is a thing hardly
known in those countries, the several difficulties relating to this
article, though of such importance with us, are with them quite out of
the question. Despotic power is self-sufficient; round it there is an
absolute vacuum. Hence it is that when travellers favour us with the
description of countries where arbitrary sway prevails, they seldom make
mention of civil laws.
[1]
All occasions, therefore, of wrangling and law-suits are here
removed. And to this in part is it owing that litigious people in those
countries are so roughly handled. As the injustice of their demand is
neither screened, palliated, nor protected by an infinite number of
laws, of course it is immediately discovered.
We hear it generally said, that justice ought to be administered
with us as in Turkey. Is it possible, then, that the most ignorant of
all nations should be the most clear-sighted on a point which it most
behoves mankind to know?
If we examine the set forms of justice with respect to the trouble
the subject undergoes in recovering his property, or in obtaining
satisfaction for an injury or affront, we shall find them doubtless too
numerous: but if we consider them in the relation they bear to the
liberty and security of every individual, we shall often find them too
few; and be convinced that the trouble, expense, delays, and even the
very dangers of our judiciary proceedings, are the price that each
subject pays for his liberty.
In Turkey, where little regard is shown to the honour, life, or
estate of the subject, all causes are speedily decided. The method of
determining them is a matter of indifference, provided they be
determined. The pasha, after a quick hearing, orders which party he
pleases to be bastinadoed, and then sends them about their business.
Here it would be dangerous to be of a litigious disposition; this
supposes a strong desire of obtaining justice, a settled aversion, an
active mind, and a steadiness in pursuing one's point. All this should
be avoided in a government where fear ought to be the only prevailing
sentiment, and in which popular disturbances are frequently attended
with sudden and unforeseen revolutions. Here every man ought to know
that the magistrate must not hear his name mentioned, and that his
security depends entirely on his being reduced to a kind of
annihilation.
But in moderate governments, where the life of the meanest subject
is deemed precious, no man is stripped of his honour or property until
after a long inquiry; and no man is bereft of life till his very country
has attacked him — an attack that is never made without leaving him all
possible means of making his defence.
Hence it is that when a person renders himself absolute,
[2]
he immediately thinks of reducing the number of laws. In a government thus
constituted they are more affected with particular inconveniences than
with the liberty of the subject, which is very little minded.
In republics, it is plain that as many formalities at least are
necessary as in monarchies. In both governments they increase in
proportion to the value which is set on the honour, fortune, liberty,
and life of the subject.
In republican governments, men are all equal; equal they are also in
despotic governments: in the former, because they are everything; in the
latter, because they are nothing.
Footnotes
[1]
In Mazulipatam it could never be found out that there was such a
thing as a written law. See the "Collection of Voyages that Contributed
to the Establishment of the East India Company," iv., part I, p. 391. The
Indians are regulated in their decisions by certain customs. The Vedan
and such books do not contain civil laws, but religious precepts. See
"Edifying Letters," coll. xiv.
[2]
Cæsar, Cromwell, and many others.